Reply to Richard Hermann
Thomas R. Demske
REFERENCE: ../mto.95.1.3/mto.95.1.3.hermann.html
KEYWORDS: similarity, atonal, post-tonal analysis, REL, evaluation
Copyright © 1995 Society for Music Theory
[1] Although I take issue with many points in Richard Hermann’s (1995) response to my essay on “similarity” relations, this reply is restricted to Hermann’s paragraphs 3–10, which I feel misrepresent my position.
[2] Hermann’s paragraphs 3 and 4 take me to task for being overly harsh on intransitivity in my footnote 3 reference to “blind subset polling.” That reference in fact alludes to information loss, and has nothing to do with transitivity. For example, REL(5-14,6-14) = REL(5-14,6-19) = REL(5-14,6-49) = 0.546, where Forte names stand for any particular instance of the named class. Here are the set classes to which abstract subsets common to each pivot and target belong:
X | Y | Z | |||||||||||||||||
REL(5-14, 6-14) | REL(5-14, 6-19) | REL(5-14, 6-49) | |||||||||||||||||
2: | 1 | 2 | 3 | 4 | 5 | 2: | 1 | 2 | 3 | 4 | 5 | 6 | 2: | 1 | 2 | 3 | 4 | 5 | 6 |
3: | 1 | 3 | 4 | 7 | 9 | 3: | 3 | 4 | 5 | 8 | 9 | 3: | 3 | 5 | 7 | 8 | |||
4: | 4 | 4: | 16 | 4: | 15 |
[3] These common subsets determine the REL values.(1) Since those values are equal, so are the spreads between each pair of values; X is to Y as X is to Z, etc. But hidden behind that sameness is an erratic divergence in the set types considered. 53% of the types used in calculating either X or Y (the union) are also used in calculating both X and Y (the intersection). 47% of the union of X and Z are also in the intersection of X and Z, and 64% of the union of Y and Z are also in the intersection of Y and Z. “Intuitively,” from this perspective, the value spreads are different. (How the difference might be interpreted is another matter; perhaps the comparison of X-Y and Y-Z spreads should command more attention than that of X-Z and Y-Z spreads?) But this perspective is lost when the intermediate steps of the calculations are discarded. It is as if we move through a hidden dimension in Rahn’s (1980) “(staggeringly complex) network” during any one REL calculation; upon obtaining the result, we burn the bridges behind us. This sort of information loss — hardly unique in music theory, but exacerbated by the remarkably restricted scope of REL’s object universe — is what the “blind subset polling” reference called into question.
[4] The “blind subset polling” reference was only a minor sidelight in my essay, relegated to a footnote. Its immediate context was the much larger problem of support through intuition, which I further addressed in a subsequent mto-talk post. I suspect that blind subset polling grates against the intuitions of others as well, and would be surprised if it did not play some part in the conception of Marcus Castren’s RECREL. In any case, transitivity is not at issue here. Nor is it especially pronounced in my paragraph 10, which Hermann also fixates upon — despite noting, in his paragraph 3, that the “t” word appears nowhere in the essay. I am nevertheless now deeply troubled by the prospect that “music will be lost,” a pathetic although curious specter raised in Hermann’s paragraph 4. Therefore, for the record, and for what it is worth: intransitivity per se does not strike me as overwhelmingly problematical.(2)
[5] Turning briefly now to the other purported “dissatisfactions” of mine which Professor Hermann illuminates in his response: An open choice of pivots is certainly not unsatisfactory in and of itself; my concern throughout the essay was instead how to guide the choice. (Hermann pars. 5–6) As for “strained intuition,” again, the context there was the elusiveness of intuition, and the inherent uncertainty of analytical models built on the shifting sands of what may or may not be significant in the abstract. (Hermann pars. 7–8) Finally, the matter of “context sensitive criteria,” which Hermann reads into my paragraph 13, is properly taken up at paragraphs 16–18; there, the question is not one of whether to acknowledge such criteria, but of how to go about identifying and incorporating them in analysis. (Hermann pars. 9–10)
[6] More passionately committed theorists may disagree, but I believe that tackling this question is possible now only on an ad hoc basis, and particularly so in the music Hermann cites in his paragraph 19. Hermann reminds us that the problem of poor results lies not necessarily [my added spin] with some given theory in itself, but rather with how knowingly that theory is applied. (Hermann’s par. 13) I agree! But the knowledge component of that formula has yet to materialize, at least with respect to “similarity” relationships (although I do applaud Hermann’s provisional sketch, and appreciate his bibliography). With no reliable constraints on the interaction between vague, “context-sensitive criteria” on one hand, and an unlimited supply of formalisms on the other, how can we rigorously evaluate any resulting analysis?
Thomas R. Demske
Yale University
Department of Music
143 Elm Street
New London, CT 06520
USA
tdemske@minerva.cis.yale.edu
Works Cited
Block, Steven and Jack Douthett. 1994. “Vector Products and Intervallic Weighting.” Journal of Music Theory 38.1 : 21–41.
Demske, Thomas R. 1995. “Relating Sets: On Considering a Computational Model of Similarity Analysis.” Music Theory Online 1.2.
—————. 1993. “Recognizing Melodic Motion in Piano Scores: Rules and Contexts.” Ph.D. diss., Yale University.
Hermann, Richard. 1995. “Towards a New Analytic Method for Post-Tonal Music: A Response to Thomas R. Demske.” Music Theory Online 1.3.
Rahn, John. 1980. “Relating Sets.” Perspectives of New Music 18.2 : 488–497.
Footnotes
1. I continue my assumption of REL taken with a full-suite TEST. Yes, as Hermann notes in his footnote 1, and as Lewin himself noted through mto-talk, REL’s original formulation allows for a more selective TEST. The next question of course is what goes into selecting a “suitable” TEST. This problem is roughly of the same cut as others discussed in the essay, and so I chose not to pursue it. Notice my footnote 4 in the essay, however, and its mention of the “arbitrarily specified standard of subset content” in Block and Douthett (1994).
Return to text
2. See my dissertation (Demske 1993, 202–208, etc.) for one practical approach to intransitivity in an applied setting.
Return to text
Copyright Statement
Copyright © 1995 by the Society for Music Theory. All rights reserved.
[1] Copyrights for individual items published in Music Theory Online (MTO) are held by their authors. Items appearing in MTO may be saved and stored in electronic or paper form, and may be shared among individuals for purposes of scholarly research or discussion, but may not be republished in any form, electronic or print, without prior, written permission from the author(s), and advance notification of the editors of MTO.
[2] Any redistributed form of items published in MTO must include the following information in a form appropriate to the medium in which the items are to appear:
This item appeared in Music Theory Online in [VOLUME #, ISSUE #] on [DAY/MONTH/YEAR]. It was authored by [FULL NAME, EMAIL ADDRESS], with whose written permission it is reprinted here.
[3] Libraries may archive issues of MTO in electronic or paper form for public access so long as each issue is stored in its entirety, and no access fee is charged. Exceptions to these requirements must be approved in writing by the editors of MTO, who will act in accordance with the decisions of the Society for Music Theory.
This document and all portions thereof are protected by U.S. and international copyright laws. Material contained herein may be copied and/or distributed for research purposes only.
Prepared by Cara Stroud, Editorial Assistant