Theories of Categorization and Theories of Music *

Lawrence M. Zbikowski



KEYWORDS: music cognition, categorization, Bruckner

ABSTRACT: Processes of categorization are known to be fundamental to human cognitive processing. This essay reviews the characteristics of two types of categories that give rise to conceptual representations. One type, which has been demonstrated to have a graded structure, is then used to model dynamic processes for thematic materials in the first movement of Bruckner’s Sixth Symphony.

PDF text | PDF examples
Volume 1, Number 4, July 1995
Copyright © 1995 Society for Music Theory


[1] In this essay I want to contemplate a relatively simple question: how do processes of categorization, which are one of the primary means by which we organize our understanding of the world, manifest themselves in our understanding of the organization of musical events? In recent years questions concerning our understanding of the organization of musical events have been treated in studies of music cognition; I shall take the position that music theory in general also deals with these questions, if not always explicitly.

[2] Eleanor Rosch and Barbara Lloyd proposed that the segmentation of the environment into classifications by means of which nonidentical stimuli can be treated as equivalent — that is, categorization — is a basic task of all organisms, and indeed, one mark of living things (1978). In general, processes of categorization appear to be a pervasive feature of human cognitive structure, extending from basic functions of perceptual discrimination through to sophisticated products of the imagination (see, for example, Edelman 1989, 1992). In the following, I shall concentrate on categorization at the level of conceptual representations, for this engages the issues most immediately relevant to music theory. Although such representations are relatively “high-level” constructs, I assume them to be intimately related to “low-level” constructs, and to share some of the same structures. In the first main section below I shall consider general features of category structure for categories that arise naturally from our interaction with our environment; of course, the specific environment I am interested in is one that includes musical events.

Example 1. Bruckner, Symphony No.6, mm.2–6

Example 1 thumbnail

(click to enlarge)

Example 2. Bruckner, Symphony No.6, mm.159–62

Example 2 thumbnail

(click to enlarge)

[3] The explicit use of theories of categorization has not played a large part in recent accounts of music cognition or in analyses of music. Exceptions are Robert Welker’s study of the abstraction of a thematic prototype from melodic variations based on the prototype (Welker 1982), and Robert Gjerdingen’s study of self-organizing neuronlike networks (Gjerdingen 1990). However, Welker views categorization as but an analogue for musical processes, and Gjerdingen’s work focuses on categorization at what is arguably a pre-conceptual level. In the second main section of this essay I shall try to show how theories of categorization can be used to model dynamic processes in music through an analysis that takes as its point of departure Carl Dahlhaus’s observations on the first movement of Anton Bruckner’s Sixth Symphony (presented in Dahlhaus 1989). Dahlhaus’s concern in these observations is with a connection between musical events that is both compelling and difficult to articulate. As one example (not discussed by Dahlhaus), consider two themes from Bruckner’s first movement; the first is given in the lower strings in measures 2–6 (see Example 1), the second in the violins and flutes in measures 159–162 (see Example 2). Is there something more than shared rhythmic profile that connects these two events, separated by well over one hundred measures, as “thematic” entities? Connections of this general sort have been a primary focus of much of the recent work on categorization, and I believe the perspective offered by theories of categorization can do much to account for some of the elusive yet persistent “intuitions” we have about musical structure.

[4] My main argument is that theories of categorization have a contribution to make both to music cognition and music theory. However, I do not believe that the relationship between cognitive theories and music is a one-way street: in a brief concluding section of this essay I shall propose that the study of music has contributions to make to theories of categorization which stem from music’s status as a temporal art form and a cultural artifact.

[5] Section 1. Most of the categorization that is crucial to our understanding of the world seems to proceed automatically and unconsciously. Current cognitive theory recognizes that some categories do indeed result from automatic, unconscious processes. However, the majority of categories that are at the level of concepts are the result of rather more complicated processes which may not occupy the center of our attention, but which are by no means automatic or unconscious. The category dog can serve as an example. We are all pretty sure we know what a dog is. This confidence is manifested in the rapidity with which we can draw a crude, stick-figure representation of a dog; in our ability to discriminate quickly and accurately between small dogs and Vietnamese pot-bellied pigs; and in our behavioral interactions with dogs. Dog, as I have described it here, represents what I shall call a Type 1 category. This sort of category is a result of our interactions with our environment, and provides the basis for actions toward and thought about the entities grouped together in the category.

[6] For social animals such as humans, our environment includes not only the physical world that surrounds us, but the actions and activities of our fellow humans as well. Type 1 categories capture regularities within our individual experience and in what we observe of others’ experience; they also reflect what we are taught by those around us. Although the establishment of a Type 1 category involves thought, it does not involve contemplation (that is, a deliberate pondering of what sort of things should go in what sort of categories); the proper domain of Type 1 categories is the sort of awareness of the world Martin Heidegger called circumspection (1962), Natsoulas calls Consciousness 3 (1978), and which Richard Shweder has called naive realism (1991). And as Hubert Dreyfus has pointed out, most of our lives are spent within just this domain of consciousness (Dreyfus 1991). Because of the immediacy and transparency of this domain of consciousness, Type 1 categories often appear to represent the way the world is, even though these categories are heavily influenced by our social environments and reflect the regularities in the physical environment that we as humans perceive (but which other species may not perceive).

[7] For general tasks of the sort I have listed the frame of reference provided by a Type 1 category is usually adequate. However, under certain circumstances a finer level of discrimination is required: sometimes we need to know the differences between a dog and a wolf. In these cases it may be necessary to specify, in some fashion, the conditions under which a large mammal is called a wolf, and under which it is called a dog. Such specification often gives rise to what I shall call a Type 2 category, membership in which is determined by a set of conditions that are individually necessary and jointly sufficient. That is, the members of Category X must have features Y and Z; if things have features Y and Z they are members of Category X. Because of their specificity, Type 2 categories often provide a basis for discourse, and for complicated, abstract, and imaginative thought about the entities grouped together in the category. Where Type 1 categories are immediate and seemingly transparent, Type 2 categories are closer to what Roger Brown has called “achievements of the imagination” (1965, 320). Type 2 categories are a result of contemplation on the constituency of categories, and are thus proper to the domain of consciousness occupied with thinking about thought — what in Heidegger is thematic consciousness (1962), what Natsoulas calls Consciousness 4 (1978), and Shweder calls artful realism (1991).

[8] In recent writing on categorization, Type 1 categories have been called natural categories, based on the emergence of this sort of category from the interaction of humans with their natural environments (see Barsalou 1992a). Type 2 categories have been called classical categories (a term that traces the heritage of the type back to Aristotle; see Smith and Medin 1981; Lakoff 1987; Barsalou 1992a; and the discussion in part I of Mechelen et al. 1993). Most evidence indicates that Type 2 categories simply represent a specialized form of Type 1 categories — take a Type 1 category, specify limits for the category through the imposition of necessary and sufficient conditions for category membership, and you’ve created a Type 2 category (however, for another view see Sutcliffe 1993).

[9] The specification of the conditions for membership in a Type 2 category results in a clear structure for the category: a given entity either is or is not a member of the category; category membership is typically an all-or- nothing affair. In the case of Type 1 categories the boundaries of membership are less clearly defined: category structure tends to be more variable. In fact, every Type 1 category studied thus far has been found to have a graded structure (Barsalou 1987, 1992a). To clarify what is meant by the notion of graded structure, let’s consider the category bird. Experimental rankings show that subjects view robins and sparrows as the best examples of birds, with owls and eagles lower down in the rankings and ostriches, emus, and penguins among the worst examples (Lakoff 1987). All are considered members of the category bird, but some better represent the category than others. Category structure is consequently graded according to typicality: category members range from the most typical to the least typical, with the former securely inside the bounds of the category (robins and sparrows) and the latter in danger of being excluded from the category (emus and penguins).(1)

[10] Since Type 1 categories are pervasive, category membership for most of the categories we use tends to be approximate and fluid. Although vexing for those who would prefer a neat and orderly view of the world, the cognitive advantages of this type of categorization are clear. When confronted with an animal that has all the characteristics of a typical dog, but lacks visible ears and a tail, we quickly categorize the creature as a sort of earless, tailless dog. We are aware that it is not a very good example of the category dog, but, thus categorized, we have a first approximation of how we should act toward it. Towards variants of other categories (“extremely large house- cat,” “miniature horse”), similar in outward appearance to members of the category dog but excluded for any number of reasons, we would act differently. The utility of Type 1 categories is immediate, the process of categorization rapid. Both features have application to the understanding of music. Given musical material and variations on that material we need not construe each variation, as well as the original material, as a separate entity, but can collect all of them within a single class (“Material X and its variations”), graded according to typicality. Because what counts as “musical material” or “variations on musical material” reflects information gathered through experience and stored in memory, categorization can be a rapid affair. Where experience is extensive, categorization can be virtually simultaneous with listening, although subject to revision on the basis of specific musical context.

[11] Although the graded structure of Type 1 categories appears to be universal, the sheer number of these categories and variation among them mitigates against a single explanation for the phenomenon of typicality, upon which grading is based. As Barsalou has noted, “It is safe to say that there are many reasons why exemplars are typical and that no single factor or invariant set of factors is solely responsible” (Barsalou 1987, 105). (The complexity of the phenomenon of typicality may be one reason Zadeh’s theory of fuzzy sets (Zadeh 1965) has met with only limited success in characterizing the structure of Type 1 categories.) One aspect of cognitive structure that contributes coherence and stability to Type 1 categories are inference structures called frames, which provide the necessary context upon which determinations of typicality are based. Even a passing consideration of frames (or frameworks) is beyond the scope of the present essay; the interested reader may consult the important and original contributions of Minsky (Minsky 1975, 1985) and Schank and Abelson (1977), or refer to the useful summaries and expansions by Barsalou (1992a, 1992b) or Barsalou and Hale (1993); I provide my own summary in Zbikowski 1991. The importance of frames for the present line of thought has to do with the account of category structure they make possible (through a recursive hierarchical system of attributes and relations for the category — see Barsalou 1992b or Barsalou et al. 1993); the constraint they impose on inference (and thus on category structure that relies on frames); on the probability that we construct new frames to deal with novel situations; and on the almost-certain absorption of frame-like structures from the culture that surrounds us (see Quinn and Holland 1987; Zbikowski 1991, chapter 4). In the following analytical section I shall model frame-like structures through sets of informal propositions; the full context for this methodology is developed in Zbikowski 1991.

[12] Categorization is a process through which we organize our understanding of the world; categories, in an important sense, are that understanding. In my own recent work I follow Barsalou 1992b, Barsalou 1993, and Barsalou et al. 1993 (and to a certain extent Edelman 1989) and regard concepts and categories as intimately related. Following a trend in the writing on cognitive science in the last decade and a half (for example, Edelman 1989; Hampton and Dubois 1993; Langacker 1987; Smith and Medin 1981; Barsalou 1992a; and Barsalou et al. 1993), I take concepts to be relatively stable information stored in long-term memory. Categories are then structured representations of perceived or imagined entities based on rules provided by concepts. Conceptualizations are temporary representations of categories in working memory (this distinction between concept and conceptualization relies on Barsalou et al. 1993). In all cases, it is assumed that these cognitive structures can stand apart from language. Although this will be a source of confusion for those used to placing concepts in privileged correspondence with linguistic entities (as Jackendoff 1987 does) it fits well with the larger picture of cognition I am interested in, and opens a path to the definition of conceptual representations specific to music and distinct from language. Simply put, conceptualizations that correspond with Type 1 categories can be pre- or para- linguistic, since the stability of the category relies not on association with a linguistic entity but instead reflects regularities within our individual experience and that of others. The experience of musicians (especially those who compose or improvise) includes sounds (both real and imagined) susceptible to stable-enough mental representation that they can become the basis for musical expression; the material transformation of these sounds into words or notation may indeed occur at some later point, but I believe these sounds do not necessarily rely on such transformation for their stability. The notion of a conceptual representation of music independent of language is indeed elusive, but I am convinced there is ample evidence we readily employ similar representations in our daily lives.(2)

[13] In the preceding I discussed two basic types of categories through which we organize our understanding of the world. Type 1 categories emerge from our interaction with our natural environment, an interaction conditioned by both culture and perception. One reflection of this interaction is the graded structure of Type 1 categories: category members are organized according to the degree to which they resemble a central exemplar or group of exemplars; what is taken as typical for a particular category appears to be constrained by frames, aspects of which are taken from culture. Type 2 categories are a result of our desire for order and for stable bases for communication; membership is determined by necessary and sufficient conditions, and category structure has clear, determinant bounds. In terms of music, the concepts associated with Type 1 categories reflect our intuitions about musical events; the concepts associated with Type 2 categories represent theoretical constructs. However, a word of caution is in order: if we have learned anything from the intense study of human cognition that has been undertaken in the last three or so decades, it is that human cognition is staggeringly complex. It goes (almost) without saying that the foregoing is a gross oversimplification of the processes of categorization that are so important for human cognition. Having said this, I nonetheless believe that the basic distinction between Type 1 and Type 2 categories is essential for understanding how we organize our understanding of musical events.

[14] Section 2. Dahlhaus’s remarks on the first movement of Bruckner’s Sixth Symphony (1881) come at a point where Dahlhaus is probing the unique way Bruckner achieved symphonic monumentality without following the path of developing variation laid out by Brahms. Dahlhaus argues that the answer lay in Bruckner’s emphasis on retaining rhythmic figuration while seeming to disregard the careful development of pitch material. After discussing two sections of the second theme that he hears as analogous (measures 53–54 and measures 61–62), Dahlhaus comments, “That the one version is able to substitute for the other means, aesthetically, that instead of developing variation, where each variant represents . . . a consequence of the preceding one and a prerequisite for the next one, Bruckner makes use of an analytically elusive but clearly perceivable similarity by association, which makes the later version seem like a written-out memory of the earlier one. The logic of discourse, as conceived by Brahms, gives way to a system of approximate correspondences” (1989, 273). The language Dahlhaus uses here — “similarity by association,” “written-out memory,” “approximate correspondences” — seems to reflect a struggle to come to terms with the “analytically elusive” basis of Bruckner’s symphonic style, given Dahlhaus’s own skepticism about the value of analyzing this music in terms of its “diastematic” (or pitch) structure: it is practically a commonplace that our conceptual framework for dealing with the comparative verities of pitch structure is well developed, but that for dealing with other aspects of music less so. I don’t intend to offer a complete, worked-out conceptual framework for dealing with these other aspects of music within the confines of the present essay. My goal is far more modest: to suggest a methodology for approaching dynamic processes in music by analyzing some of the thematic material from Bruckner’s first movement as a Type 1 category. By this means I hope to show that Bruckner achieves symphonic monumentality, in part, through a process that draws wide-spread “blocks” of material (as Dahlhaus characterized them) into dynamic categorical relationships.

[15] I shall consider the first main theme (measures 3–6, with pickup) of the work to be a category structured by four informal propositions (3):

  • (P1) The rhythmic figuration of the theme consists of events the notation for which (in cut time) would be (a) two half notes, preceded by a sixteenth-note pickup; followed by (b) a triplet-quarter-note rest, five triplet-quarter-notes, a dotted half, a quarter, a half note and a half rest.
  • (P2) The first interval of the theme is a falling fifth.
  • (P3) The overall contour of the theme (reckoned in directed pitch intervals) is as follows: 0 -7 -2 +2 +1 -1 -2 +2 +8 -1.
  • (P4) The theme is stated by a unified group or choir of instruments in relief against an accompanimental pattern.

The actual intervals of the contour of the theme recorded in P3 are, of course, not essential to the general notion of contour; I list them here as a means of compactly representing the contour of the theme and to facilitate further comparisons.(4) The importance of P4 is arguable: I introduce it to strengthen the notion of "theme," and to exclude the echo of the final portion of the theme by the horn in measures 7–8. (I shall comment on this exclusion below.)

[16] It should be noted that the structure of the category does not rely on a specification of scale step, and does not, for that matter, invoke a diatonic frame of reference (except in the characterization of P2’s interval as a “fifth”). Neither pitch class or pitch (the latter including an indication of register) are specified. All of these things, as well as others, could be specified in the structure of the category should they be deemed essential to the characterization of musical material. The category also relies on background models — in particular, that there are such things as musical works, and that musical works have clearly identifiable “themes” that stand out against “accompaniments,” and that such themes are important for musical structure. The assumption, then, is that the given propositions model an understanding of the musical material associated with the frame for this particular category of musical events, and that this understanding is part of a contextual understanding gleaned from encounters with this piece and with the broader repertoire of which it is a part (for further discussion see Zbikowski 1991, chapters 5 and 6).

Example 3. Bruckner, Symphony No.6, mm.8–12

Example 3 thumbnail

(click to enlarge)

Figure 1. Contour comparison of directed pitch intervals in the first movement of Bruckner’s Sixth Symphony, exposition

Figure 1 thumbnail

(click to enlarge)

[17] The second thematic statement, in measures 8–12 (see Example 3), meets P1, P2, and P4, but does not meet P3; a comparison of the contour of the two passages (again given in directed pitch intervals) is given in Figure 1. As can be seen, the contour pattern of the third through seventh intervals of the second thematic statement is the reverse of the pattern of the first thematic statement. In the following, I shall offer an informal ranking of typicality according to the number of structural propositions met (and the completeness with which they are met) by each thematic statement: if measures 2–6 are typical of the category that constitutes the theme of this movement, measures 8–12 are less somewhat typical. I should note that my ranking of typicality, here and in the following, is intended only as a guide to category structure; it is by no means the case that the first statement of musical material is always the most typical, although this is a strategy often used by composers. A further consideration of some of the factors impinging on typicality is taken up below.

[18] The next thematic statement, which occurs in measures 24–28, is an orchestrally reinforced version of measures 2–6. Because it meets the structural propositions for the category we can consider it to be typical. It is followed, in measures 30–34, by a similar restatement of the less-typical measures 8–12. However, embedded in the orchestral detail of both statements are quasi- imitative statements of thematic material in the horns (measures 26–28 and measures 32–34). These statements each represent only one of the structural propositions completely (P2); P1 and P3 are met partially, and P4 is not met at all. They are consequently even less typical versions of the theme. Finally, in measures 35–36, the horns state the head of the theme; here, P2 and P4 are realized completely, but P1 and P3 are met almost not at all. In the informal ranking I have offered, it might be argued that these fragmentary gestures are actually slightly more typical of the category that constitutes the theme than the more-complete statements in measures 26–28 and measures 32–34. Although this does violence to our basic intuition that, for the purposes of representing the identity of musical material, more is better, it does throw the thematic aspect of the theme (that is, that portion of the musical notion of a theme that has correspondences to the theme as subject of discourse, literary or otherwise) into relief: measures 26–28 and measures 32–34 may be more complete, but they lose the competition for our attention in the welter of information with which we are beset, and thus fail as a subject or topic.

[19] With the final, fragmentary statements of thematic material in the horns Bruckner departs for other musical ground. He does not return to his introductory material until well into the movement, and then only shortly before the recapitulation of his opening ideas. The first intimation of this return (as was the last gesture of departure) is given again to the horns: in measures 147 and 148 they state the falling fifth of the theme in half notes. In terms of categorical structure, P2 is realized, P1 and P3 are met almost not at all, and P4 is only partially met, and rather weakly (in that the triplet- quarter-note figures in the strings are strongly associated with the second theme group, and are thus somewhat less “accompanimental”). With regard to typicality, these statements of thematic material are the least typical of those I have considered.

Figure 2. Contour comparison of directed pitch intervals in the first movement of Bruckner’s Sixth Symphony, exposition and end of development

Figure 2 thumbnail

(click to enlarge)

[20] In measures 159–62 Bruckner begins in earnest the process of returning to his opening ideas. The thematic material stated here at first only faintly resembles the theme: although P4 is met and P1 is almost perfectly realized (the only lack being the sixteenth-note pickup), P2 (which was of importance for the fragmentary statements of the theme discussed above) is not met (the opening leap is not a fifth in descent, but an octave in ascent), nor is P3. Or, if P3 is met, it is in a rather unusual and convoluted way: if we compare the contour of measures 159–62 with that of measures 3–6 (not including the pickup) we find an exact mirror of the pattern of the contour (see Figure 2). The typicality of this statement, within the category of thematic material, ranks with the fragmentary statements of measures 26–36, and sounds as something fainter than what Dahlhaus called a “written-out memory” of the earlier material.

[21] What happens next is striking, especially in terms of the musical analysis by way of processes of categorization I have undertaken here. Where only four more-or-less complete versions of thematic material were presented in the opening thirty-six measures (two typical [measures 2–6 and 24–28], two less typical [measures 8–12 and 30–34]), in the twenty-odd measures that follow measure 159 Bruckner presents six versions of thematic material, all highly similar to that given in measures 159–62. These six statements could even be viewed as forming their own category, with a structure strongly related to that of the first category proposed above. The structural propositions for this second category would be as follows:

  • (P1) The rhythmic figuration of the theme consists of events the notation for which (in cut time) would be (a) two half notes, preceded by a sixteenth-note pickup; followed by (b) a triplet-quarter-note rest, five triplet-quarter-notes, a dotted half, a quarter, a half note and a half rest.
  • (P2n) The first interval of the theme is an ascending octave.
  • (P3n) The contour of the theme (reckoned in directed pitch intervals) is as follows: 0 +12 +2 -2 -3 +3 +2 -2 -9 +1.
  • (P4) The theme is stated by a unified group or choir of instruments in relief against an accompanimental pattern.

Figure 3. Contour comparison of directed pitch intervals in the first movement of Bruckner’s Sixth Symphony, end of development

Figure 3 thumbnail

(click to enlarge)

Of course, P1 and P4 are identical to P1 and P4 in the first category. With regard to the new propositions, P2n addresses the new opening interval, and P3n is a strengthened version of P3, reflecting that the only differences between the six thematic statements are the size of interval for the first nine intervals, and the direction and size of the last interval (see Figure 3). Again, typicality effects can be observed: one ranking might take the first and fifth statements as most typical of the category, the sixth and second as somewhat less typical, and the third and fourth as least typical. (The matter of the typicality of measures 159–62, which does not have a sixteenth-note pickup, will be addressed below.)

[22] Are these six thematic statements in fact a category independent of, yet related to, the first category? The answer depends, to a large extent, on what one hears as typical, and how typicality emerges; to expand on this a little, I offer the following observations. I hear the first statement in measures 159–62 as a pale, awkward reminiscence of the theme, most strongly related through rhythmic figuration and thematic status — I find I really miss the half-step of the written-out turn of measures 2–6 and 24–28. However, as this new version is restated (in its variant forms) I find it more and more believable, such that at the point of its abandonment in measure 182 it seems a thing worthy of thematic status. The change in my attitude could be attributed to the more- or-less simple, successive repetition of the rhythmic figure, clad in slowly changing pitches. However, it could also be attributed to the cycle of typicality the material is taken through. The cycle starts with typical material (statements one and two), ventures into less typical material (statements three and four), and then returns to typical material (statements five and six). The reaffirmation of typicality accomplished by the statement of the transposed version of measures 159–62 in measures 175–78 can be seen as a way of revealing that the earlier measures were no accident (that is, not a pale, awkward reminiscence of the theme), but were in fact exactly what the composer wanted at that point. The contrast provided by the less-typical material serves to emphasize this revelation.

[23] As viable as the modified thematic material of measures 159–82 may seem at measure 182, within the context of the movement as a whole the impression of viability is but an illusion (although an important one). A transformed version of the transitional material first heard in measures 15–24 leads, through the course of measures 183–94, to a magnificent reprise of the opening theme in the full orchestral tutti following measure 195. For the remainder of the movement the echo figures of measures 7–8, 13–14, and 29–30 are absent; the absence of these figures in the latter portion of the movement is one reason the structure of the category for the theme excludes them. Typicality here reflects the overall “environment” of the movement, and accommodates repeated passes through this environment. An analysis that would read the theme together with its echo (measures 3–8 inclusive) as typical is possible, but seems a distortion given the context of the entire movement. A more interesting alternative would be one that takes both measures 3–6 and 9–12 as typical, resulting in a binary basis for typicality. I have opted for a somewhat less complicated analysis which reflects my current hearing of the movement and which permits me an overall analysis I find intriguing. Similarly, I readily hear a match between measures 159–62 and measures 175–78 (even though the former lacks the characteristic sixteenth-note pickup of the theme), and consequently rank them both as typical.

[24] Given these thoughts, my preferred reading of categorical structure would subsume the thematic material of measures 159–82 under the basic category of the theme. This subsumption need not suppress the intriguing cycle of typicality manifested within these measures, but only subordinate it to the larger pattern played out across the entire range of category members. And it is on this larger pattern that I now want to focus, for I believe it makes a significant contribution to the monumentality observed by Dahlhaus. As Dahlhaus observed, Bruckner tends to present thematic material in rhythmically distinct blocks, favoring a system of approximate correspondences over the logic of discourse associated with developing variation. The material of these blocks tends to be static, but in a complicated way. Although there is motion away from thematic material (and the cognitive stability that typicality represents), there is always a return as well: blocks tend to be “about” thematic material. There is also an enormous amount of surface rhythmic activity (especially at the reprise following measure 195), but it is made up of consistent and recurrent patterns. The result of both these features is agitated material that tends to move only within circumscribed limits: to stay within its “block.” However, there is a larger process at work as well, one that is anything but static. In the opening thirty-six measures Bruckner introduces thematic material, which he then neglects for over one hundred measures. When he does return to it (in measure 159), it is in a veiled, atypical form. This form then presses forward into our awareness, threatening to supplant the memory of the earlier, “original,” version. The stage is then set for a triumphant and massive return of the original material, vanquishing the pretender to the thematic throne as it claims its right. Bruckner’s strategy, as I read it, differs from the conventions of sonata form it presupposes in two important ways. First, the variant material vanquished by the return of the theme is “developed” only in the most minimal sense: it clearly lacks the contingency associated with developmental strategies. Second, the triumphant return of the theme is not coordinated with a return to the original key of the first theme. Given the progress of the movement as a whole, I find it difficult to argue that the statement of the theme in the original key following measure 209 is somehow more dramatic or, at that moment, cognitively more significant than the statement that starts in measure 195.

[25] In the analysis I have offered here, I have supposed that musical events are susceptible to categorization, and that these categories show typicality effects. Although I have reflected category structure in terms of informal propositions, my assumption is that a listener would arrive at this category without recourse to even these informal formalizations — musical categorization instead goes on quickly and without seeming effort, unless one is in an unusual musical environment. I have interpreted the typicality effects that categories show in terms of a dynamic model, wherein the most typical category member is stable, and the least typical is unstable. This then leads to a reading of one aspect of the dynamic profile of Bruckner’s first movement as a pattern of typical material yielding to less typical material, which in turn yields to the typical. The movement as a whole, then, plays out the cycle of typicality discussed in connection with measures 159–82. Thus Bruckner makes use of a system of approximate correspondences and exact correspondences, playing out in a dynamic process stretched over close to ten minutes, to achieve symphonic monumentality.

[26] Section 3. My argument has been that theories of categorization have a contribution to make both to music cognition and to music theory. For music cognition, theories of categorization offer one way of describing how musical events are grouped together, which in turn provides a basis for describing how one group of musical events relates to another. For music theory, theories of categorization offer a way to model musical process as a set of dynamic (and temporally bounded) relationships that obtain among groups of musical events. However, I believe the study of how processes of categorization can be applied to our understanding of music has at least two contributions to make to cognitive theory. First, categorical processes adequate to music must deal with a large amount of auditory information streaming by in real time, which requires a model of categorization that is extremely rapid (at least in its gross aspects) and highly flexible. Second, since music is a cultural artifact the structure of musical categories must reflect the influence of culture in some way; it would appear, based on preliminary investigations, that the relationship between categorization and frame-like structures will be extremely important in this connection. I feel confident that there are rewards for both the study of music cognition and the study of processes of categorization in a consideration of how it is we understand music. Music, at its best, speaks with immediacy and import to the core of our being, and categorization, as one of the most fundamental of cognitive processes, seems destined to be associated with this immediacy and import.

    Return to beginning    



Lawrence M. Zbikowski
University of Chicago
Department of Music
Goodspeed Hall
1010 East 59th Street
Chicago, IL 60615
L-ZBIKOWSKI@UCHICAGO.EDU

    Return to beginning    



Works Cited

Barsalou, Lawrence W. 1987. The instability of graded structure: Implications for the nature of concepts. In Concepts and conceptual development: Ecological and intellectual factors in categorization, ed. Ulric Neisser, 101–40. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Barsalou, Lawrence W. 1987. The instability of graded structure: Implications for the nature of concepts. In Concepts and conceptual development: Ecological and intellectual factors in categorization, ed. Ulric Neisser, 101–40. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Barsalou, Lawrence W. 1992a. Cognitive psychology: An overview for cognitive scientists. Hillsdale, N.J.: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

—————. 1992a. Cognitive psychology: An overview for cognitive scientists. Hillsdale, N.J.: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

Barsalou, Lawrence W. 1992b. Frames, concepts, and conceptual fields. In Frames, fields, and contrasts: New essays in semantic and lexical organization, ed. Adrienne Lehrer and Eva Feder Kittay, 21–74. Hillsdale, N.J.: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

—————. 1992b. Frames, concepts, and conceptual fields. In Frames, fields, and contrasts: New essays in semantic and lexical organization, ed. Adrienne Lehrer and Eva Feder Kittay, 21–74. Hillsdale, N.J.: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

Barsalou, Lawrence W. 1993. Flexibility, structure, and linguistic vagary in concepts: Manifestations of a compositional system of perceptual symbols. In Theories of memory, ed. A. F. Collins, S. E. Gathercole, M. A. Conway, and Morris P. E, 29–101. Hillsdale, N.J.: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

—————. 1993. Flexibility, structure, and linguistic vagary in concepts: Manifestations of a compositional system of perceptual symbols. In Theories of memory, ed. A. F. Collins, S. E. Gathercole, M. A. Conway, and Morris P. E, 29–101. Hillsdale, N.J.: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

Barsalou, Lawrence W., and Christopher R. Hale. 1993. Components of conceptual representation: From feature lists to recursive frames. In Categories and concepts: Theoretical views and inductive analysis, ed. Iven van Mechelen, James Hampton, Ryszard S. Michalski, and Peter Theuns, 97–144. Cognitive Science Series. London: Academic Press.

Barsalou, Lawrence W., and Christopher R. Hale. 1993. Components of conceptual representation: From feature lists to recursive frames. In Categories and concepts: Theoretical views and inductive analysis, ed. Iven van Mechelen, James Hampton, Ryszard S. Michalski, and Peter Theuns, 97–144. Cognitive Science Series. London: Academic Press.

Barsalou, Lawrence W., Wenchi Yeh, Barbara J. Luka, Karen L. Olseth, Kelly S. Mix, and Ling-Ling Wu. 1993. Concepts and meaning. In Chicago Linguistics Society 29: Papers from the parasession on conceptual representations, ed. K. Beals, G. Cooke, D. Kathman, K. E. McCullough, S. Kita, and D. Testen. Chicago: University of Chicago, Chicago Linguistics Society.

Barsalou, Lawrence W., Wenchi Yeh, Barbara J. Luka, Karen L. Olseth, Kelly S. Mix, and Ling-Ling Wu. 1993. Concepts and meaning. In Chicago Linguistics Society 29: Papers from the parasession on conceptual representations, ed. K. Beals, G. Cooke, D. Kathman, K. E. McCullough, S. Kita, and D. Testen. Chicago: University of Chicago, Chicago Linguistics Society.

Brown, Roger. 1965. Social psychology. New York: Free Press.

Brown, Roger. 1965. Social psychology. New York: Free Press.

Dahlhaus, Carl. 1989. Nineteenth-century music. Trans. J. Bradford Robinson. Berkeley: University of California Press.

Dahlhaus, Carl. 1989. Nineteenth-century music. Trans. J. Bradford Robinson. Berkeley: University of California Press.

Dreyfus, Hubert L. 1991. Being-in-the-world: A commentary on Heidegger's Being and Time, Division I. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

Dreyfus, Hubert L. 1991. Being-in-the-world: A commentary on Heidegger's Being and Time, Division I. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

Edelman, Gerald M. 1989. The remembered present: A biological theory of consciousness. New York: Basic Books.

Edelman, Gerald M. 1989. The remembered present: A biological theory of consciousness. New York: Basic Books.

Edelman, Gerald M. 1992. Bright air, brilliant fire: On the matter of mind. New York: Basic Books.

—————. 1992. Bright air, brilliant fire: On the matter of mind. New York: Basic Books.

Friedmann, Michael L. 1985. A methodology for the discussion of contour: Its application to Schoenberg's music. Journal of Music Theory 29 (Fall):223–48.

Friedmann, Michael L. 1985. A methodology for the discussion of contour: Its application to Schoenberg's music. Journal of Music Theory 29 (Fall):223–48.

Gjerdingen, Robert O. 1990. Categorization of musical patterns by self-organizing neuronlike networks. Music Perception 7 (Summer):339–70.

Gjerdingen, Robert O. 1990. Categorization of musical patterns by self-organizing neuronlike networks. Music Perception 7 (Summer):339–70.

Hampton, James. 1993. Prototype models of concept representation. In Categories and concepts: Theoretical views and inductive analysis, ed. Iven van Mechelen, James Hampton, Ryszard S. Michalski, and Peter Theuns, 67–95. Cognitive Science Series. London: Academic Press.

Hampton, James. 1993. Prototype models of concept representation. In Categories and concepts: Theoretical views and inductive analysis, ed. Iven van Mechelen, James Hampton, Ryszard S. Michalski, and Peter Theuns, 67–95. Cognitive Science Series. London: Academic Press.

Hampton, James, and Daniele Dubois. 1993. Psychological models of concepts. In Categories and concepts: Theoretical views and inductive analysis, ed. Iven van Mechelen, James Hampton, Ryszard S. Michalski, and Peter Theuns, 11–33. Cognitive Science Series. London: Academic Press.

Hampton, James, and Daniele Dubois. 1993. Psychological models of concepts. In Categories and concepts: Theoretical views and inductive analysis, ed. Iven van Mechelen, James Hampton, Ryszard S. Michalski, and Peter Theuns, 11–33. Cognitive Science Series. London: Academic Press.

Heidegger, Martin. 1962. Being and time. Trans. John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson. New York: Harper-Collins Publishers.

Heidegger, Martin. 1962. Being and time. Trans. John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson. New York: Harper-Collins Publishers.

Jackendoff, Ray. 1987. Consciousness and the computational mind. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

Jackendoff, Ray. 1987. Consciousness and the computational mind. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

Lakoff, George. 1987. Women, fire, and dangerous things: What categories reveal about the mind. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Lakoff, George. 1987. Women, fire, and dangerous things: What categories reveal about the mind. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Langacker, Ronald W. 1987. Foundations of cognitive grammar: Theoretical prerequisites. Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press.

Langacker, Ronald W. 1987. Foundations of cognitive grammar: Theoretical prerequisites. Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press.

Lerdahl, Fred, and Ray Jackendoff. 1983. A generative theory of tonal music. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

Lerdahl, Fred, and Ray Jackendoff. 1983. A generative theory of tonal music. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

Mechelen, Iven van, James Hampton, Ryszard S. Michalski, and Peter Theuns, eds. 1993. Categories and concepts: Theoretical views and inductive analysis. London: Academic Press.

Mechelen, Iven van, James Hampton, Ryszard S. Michalski, and Peter Theuns, eds. 1993. Categories and concepts: Theoretical views and inductive analysis. London: Academic Press.

Minsky, Marvin. 1975. A framework for representing knowledge. In The psychology of computer vision, ed. Patrick Henry Winston, 211–77. New York: McGraw-Hill.

Minsky, Marvin. 1975. A framework for representing knowledge. In The psychology of computer vision, ed. Patrick Henry Winston, 211–77. New York: McGraw-Hill.

Minsky, Marvin. 1985. The society of mind. New York: Simon and Schuster.

—————. 1985. The society of mind. New York: Simon and Schuster.

Morris, Robert D. 1987. Composition with pitch classes: A theory of compositional design. New Haven: Yale University Press.

Morris, Robert D. 1987. Composition with pitch classes: A theory of compositional design. New Haven: Yale University Press.

Natsoulas, T. 1978. Consciousness. American Psychologist 33: 906–14.

Natsoulas, T. 1978. Consciousness. American Psychologist 33: 906–14.

Quinn, Naomi, and Dorothy Holland. 1987. Culture and cognition. In Cultural models in language and thought, ed. Dorothy Holland and Naomi Quinn, 3–40. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Quinn, Naomi, and Dorothy Holland. 1987. Culture and cognition. In Cultural models in language and thought, ed. Dorothy Holland and Naomi Quinn, 3–40. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Rosch, Eleanor, and Barbara B. Lloyd. 1978. Introduction. In Cognition and categorization, ed. Eleanor Rosch and Barbara B. Lloyd. Hillsdale, N.J.: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

Rosch, Eleanor, and Barbara B. Lloyd. 1978. Introduction. In Cognition and categorization, ed. Eleanor Rosch and Barbara B. Lloyd. Hillsdale, N.J.: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

Rosch, Eleanor, and Carolyn B. Mervis. 1975. Family resemblances. Cognitive Psychology 7: 573–605.

Rosch, Eleanor, and Carolyn B. Mervis. 1975. Family resemblances. Cognitive Psychology 7: 573–605.

Schank, Roger C., and Robert P. Abelson. 1977. Scripts, plans, goals and understanding: An inquiry into human knowledge structures. Hillsdale, N.J.: Lawrence Erlbaum.

Schank, Roger C., and Robert P. Abelson. 1977. Scripts, plans, goals and understanding: An inquiry into human knowledge structures. Hillsdale, N.J.: Lawrence Erlbaum.

Shweder, Richard A. 1991. Thinking through cultures: Expeditions in cultural psychology. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.

Shweder, Richard A. 1991. Thinking through cultures: Expeditions in cultural psychology. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.

Smith, Edward E., and Douglas L. Medin. 1981. Categories and concepts. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.

Smith, Edward E., and Douglas L. Medin. 1981. Categories and concepts. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.

Sutcliffe, John Philip. 1993. Concept, class and category in the tradition of Aristotle. In Categories and concepts: Theoretical views and inductive analysis, ed. Iven van Mechelen, James Hampton, Ryszard S. Michalski, and Peter Theuns, 35–65. Cognitive Science Series. London: Academic Press.

Sutcliffe, John Philip. 1993. Concept, class and category in the tradition of Aristotle. In Categories and concepts: Theoretical views and inductive analysis, ed. Iven van Mechelen, James Hampton, Ryszard S. Michalski, and Peter Theuns, 35–65. Cognitive Science Series. London: Academic Press.

Welker, Robert L. 1982. Abstraction of themes from melodic variations. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance 8(3):435–47.

Welker, Robert L. 1982. Abstraction of themes from melodic variations. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance 8(3):435–47.

Zadeh, Lofti. 1965. Fuzzy sets. Information and Control 8: 338–53.

Zadeh, Lofti. 1965. Fuzzy sets. Information and Control 8: 338–53.

Zbikowski, Lawrence. 1991. “Large-scale rhythm and systems of grouping.” Ph. D. Diss. Yale University.

Zbikowski, Lawrence. 1991. “Large-scale rhythm and systems of grouping.” Ph. D. Diss. Yale University.

    Return to beginning    



Footnotes

* I would like to acknowledge the suggestions and comments of Robert Cook of the University of Chicago and the anonymous reviewer for Music Theory Online; these contributed significantly to the final form of this essay.
Return to text

I would like to acknowledge the suggestions and comments of Robert Cook of the University of Chicago and the anonymous reviewer for Music Theory Online; these contributed significantly to the final form of this essay.

1. Following the work of Rosch and Mervis 1975, Lakoff 1987 and others have called categories with a graded structure “prototype-effect categories,” where the prototype is the most typical member of the category, and prototype- effects are those of grading. For a discussion of prototype models see Hampton 1993.
Return to text

2. I am reminded here of Augustine’s central conceptual pivot in his remarks on time in his Confessions (Book XI, Chapter XIV): “What, then, is time? If no one asks of me, I know; if I wish to explain it to him who asks, I know not.”
Return to text

3. Although I believethere are good reasons for isolating the “theme” as I do here, they rely on aspects of categorization I did not discuss in Section 1. In particular, basic-level categories and what I have called m-categories are important (see Zbikowski 1991); aspects of the latter have connections to Lerdahl and Jackendoff’s notion of a group (1983).
Return to text

4. Basic discussions of contour can be found in Friedmann 1985 and Morris 1987.
Return to text

Following the work of Rosch and Mervis 1975, Lakoff 1987 and others have called categories with a graded structure “prototype-effect categories,” where the prototype is the most typical member of the category, and prototype- effects are those of grading. For a discussion of prototype models see Hampton 1993.
I am reminded here of Augustine’s central conceptual pivot in his remarks on time in his Confessions (Book XI, Chapter XIV): “What, then, is time? If no one asks of me, I know; if I wish to explain it to him who asks, I know not.”
Although I believethere are good reasons for isolating the “theme” as I do here, they rely on aspects of categorization I did not discuss in Section 1. In particular, basic-level categories and what I have called m-categories are important (see Zbikowski 1991); aspects of the latter have connections to Lerdahl and Jackendoff’s notion of a group (1983).
Basic discussions of contour can be found in Friedmann 1985 and Morris 1987.
    Return to beginning    



Copyright Statement

Copyright © 1995 by the Society for Music Theory. All rights reserved.

[1] Copyrights for individual items published in Music Theory Online (MTO) are held by their authors. Items appearing in MTO may be saved and stored in electronic or paper form, and may be shared among individuals for purposes of scholarly research or discussion, but may not be republished in any form, electronic or print, without prior, written permission from the author(s), and advance notification of the editors of MTO.

[2] Any redistributed form of items published in MTO must include the following information in a form appropriate to the medium in which the items are to appear:

This item appeared in Music Theory Online in [VOLUME #, ISSUE #] on [DAY/MONTH/YEAR]. It was authored by [FULL NAME, EMAIL ADDRESS], with whose written permission it is reprinted here.

[3] Libraries may archive issues of MTO in electronic or paper form for public access so long as each issue is stored in its entirety, and no access fee is charged. Exceptions to these requirements must be approved in writing by the editors of MTO, who will act in accordance with the decisions of the Society for Music Theory.

This document and all portions thereof are protected by U.S. and international copyright laws. Material contained herein may be copied and/or distributed for research purposes only.

    Return to beginning    


                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                       
SMT

Prepared by Cara Stroud, Editorial Assistant