Analyzing Music Under the New Musicological Regime
Kofi Agawu
KEYWORDS: analysis, music theory, Adorno, new musicology
Copyright © 1996 Society for Music Theory
[1] Analysis has always played a role in musicology. “The analytical process,” writes Arnold Whittall, and echoing a generation of structuralists, “is two-fold: to identify the various materials of a composition, and to define the ways in which they function.”(1) Thus defined, analysis is indispensable to a discipline that takes the musical object as its point of departure. Not all branches of musicology demand a vigorous deployment of analytical techniques. And this is in part because not all branches of musicology are directly concerned with the experience of music. Attending to the archive (not canon) of musical works is, however, impossible without analytical mediation, itself propped up by an explicit or—more likely—implicit theory.
[2] Analysis plays an even more central role in the discipline of Music Theory. Traditionally defined, theory undertakes to codify “the various materials of a composition” and to exemplify their functioning in a range of works; it insists that its methods meet explicitly stated criteria of coherence; and it often proclaims aesthetic preferences, though not always directly. In a little-known essay published posthumously, Adorno reflects upon the potential of music analysis. Reading notation, for example, requires “an analytical act”; analysis is “the prerequisite for an adequate performance”, and aesthetic theories on music are “inconceivable without analysis.” Perhaps most important of all, analysis “has to do with the surplus [das Mehr] in art,” this surplus being the “truth content” of a work in so far as it goes beyond the mere facts. “No analysis,” Adorno writes, “is of any value if it does not terminate in the truth content of the work, and this, for its part, is mediated through the work’s technical structure”.(2)
[3] Not all areas of theory need analysis, but by and large the majority of scholars who regard themselves as ‘theorists’ or ‘analysts’ or ‘practicing analysts’ are often engaged in a more or less systematic inquiry into the structure of ‘the music itself.’ Analysis allows practitioners to come to grips with “the detail of a musical whole.”(3) Its rewards, like those of musical performance, stem from a hands-on experience. Although it makes claims about knowledge (here the differences between analysis and theory are noteworthy), an analysis does not merely produce a detached set of results available in verbal form. This is neither to mystify the analytical process nor to claim for it transcendent status; it is rather to remind us of the easily forgotten fact that there are different kinds of musical knowledge, and that these are constituted in a complex variety of ways.
[4] Analysis, finally, is a relatively young discipline. According to Ian Bent, analysis “as a pursuit in its own right, came to be established only in the late 19th century.”(4) Although codified analytical methods date back at least to the eighteenth century, and although the refinement and formalization of techniques in our own century have depended directly on those earlier developments, it is perhaps more than merely coincidental that not until the 1980s did the first comprehensive guides to analytical techniques in English appear: Ian Bent’s Grove spin off, Analysis (1980/1987); Nicholas Cook’s A Guide to Musical Analysis (1987); and Jonathan Dunsby and Arnold Whittall’s Music Analysis in Theory and Practice (1988). Intended in part to meet a pedagogical need, these books take full advantage of the specialized studies of previous decades in order to consolidate analytical knowledge. The stage was now set, it seemed, for exploring the range of applicability of various techniques, for interrogating their foundations, and for assessing their limitations.
[5] Before this intra-disciplinary self-examination could play itself out, however, the young discipline of analysis came under attack. In “How We Got Into Analysis and How to Get Out” published in 1980, Joseph Kerman asked theorists some tough questions, and then proceeded to elevate his own brand of criticism to a position of privilege among the competing discourses about music.(5) Although he recognized criticism’s debt to analysis, Kerman nevertheless placed a higher premium on a research enterprise that did not terminate either in the gathering of facts or in the establishment of a work’s internal relationships. His book of five years later, Contemplating Music, enabled a crystallization of the offending categories as ‘positivism’ and ‘formalism’.(6) Although these terms carry considerable semantic and ideological baggage, their complex histories were subsequently suppressed in the drive to inform about the limitations of theory-based analysis. The charge of formalism was made because analysts inquired only into the connections between patterns within a piece; they did not deal with matters of affect and expression, with the ‘meaning’ of music, with its cultural context. This unfortunate misrepresentation of a hitherto complex theoretical enterprise made possible the prescription of an instant cure. To escape the dilemmas of formalism, you must attach the patterns you have observed to something else: a plot, a program, an emotional scenario, a context, an agenda, a fantasy, or a narrative. You must, in other words, problematize the gap between the musical and the extra-musical. The findings of formalist analysis are like a severed phallus; ideally, they should be re-attached.(7)
[6] It was in this anti-formalist climate that the so-called ‘new musicology’ emerged. To say that they are united in their anti-formalist stance may not please the new musicologists, for an essential part of their strategy is to deny any stable, collective identity, to insist on the impossibility of anchoring the first signifying relationship. Such denial is understandable in light of the different initiatives that are gradually coalescing into a ‘new musicology.’ But could such denial also be a trick aimed at ensuring that new musicologists are always able to shift their identities in order to, as it were, remain on top?
[7] What, then, is the new musicology? In her 1994 presidential address to the American Musicological Society, Ellen Rosand took note of “new approaches to music, most of them developed in other fields.” She writes, “Semiotics, response and reception theory, narratology, gender theory, cultural criticism—these are just some of the analytical approaches that have been newly brought to bear on the study of music. And the result is a conglomeration of critical activities commonly called the ‘new musicology.’”(8) The new musicology is, in short, eclectic and selectively pluralistic.(9)
[8] Rosand’s “The Musicology of the Present,” with its subtle suppression of any prophetic claims, and its even-handed review of current musicological activity, challenges but also reinforces the substance of an article published two years earlier under the unabashed title, “The Musicology of the Future.”(10) Lawrence Kramer admits that “the new conceptual modes are too motley a grouping to form a school, and too critical of grand syntheses to admit of one.” He nevertheless offers the single most forthright statement about the new musicology that I have come across. Kramer’s is not a casual invitation to interested music scholars to sample some new products. On the contrary, it is nothing less than a prophecy about the death of musicology. In order to survive, musicology must embrace a network of “postmodernist strategies of understanding”. And despite his words to the contrary, Kramer’s enumeration reads like a manifesto: “The theories that ground [postmodernist] strategies are radically anti-foundationalist, anti-essentialist, and anti-totalizing. They emphasize the constructedness, both linguistic and ideological, of all human identities and institutions. They insist on the relativity of all knowledge to the disciplines—not just the conceptual presuppositions but the material, discursive, and social practices—that produce and circulate knowledge. While often disagreeing with each other, poststructuralists, neopragmatists, feminists, psychoanalytic theorists, critical social theorists, multiculturalists and others have been changing the very framework within which disagreement can meaningfully occur.”(11) To give up essentialist, foundationalist and totalizing discourses is to radically rethink the basic task of representation. A simple—though I hope not simplistic—account of Kramer’s statement may be given as follows. We should now accept that there are no nuggets of identity, no positivisms, no irreducible essences. There are no invariant first principles, no God or universal reason, no single grand narratives by which human history can be conceptualized. Our epistemologies are constructed and situated. Everything is fragmented and discontinuous; all truths are partial and provisional. Nothing is ever objective, nothing is ever ‘new,’ and nothing can be taken for granted. This bold attempt to wipe the slate clean is, of course, salutary, a long overdue and a much-needed initiative to liberate musicology (and music theory) from their ostensible conservatism and complacency. If we read Kramer’s statement as a call to action rather than as a summary of existing scholarship, if in other words we detach its political motivation from the cogency of its epistemology, then it is hard to imagine any worthwhile opposition to his vision of a new musicology.
[9] To the question, What has the new musicology achieved so far?, one answer may be that it has fostered what is often presented as a new way of construing cultural objects. Politically-motivated criticism is in; issues of race, gender construction and sexuality that impinge on the consumption of music are very much in. Non-canonical repertoires, especially of the popular variety, are in. The reception of music, understood not necessarily as an account of other listening subjects (with specific histories and geographies), but as an account developed around the individual subject, is in in a big way. One’s insights need not meet the test of intersubjective corroboration; nor do they need to be propped up by what is often presented as an over-determined theory-based analysis. The fantasies set in motion by biography, be it that of composer, performer, or listening subject, need no longer be suppressed or even understated. And the language in which all of this is mediated is best if it highlights the performative element in writing—charged, colorful, sometimes obscure sometimes playful, but never clinical or ‘scientific.’
[10] Which brings us to the question of analysis. Since analysis is associated with formalism, and since the new musicology is, among other things, an anti-formalist movement, and since the discipline of theory is constituted in large measure by practicing analysts, it would seem that the aims of theory and the new musicology are fundamentally incompatible. Is there any way in which music theory can embrace the positive tenets of the new musicology and still give due attention to what Adorno called the ‘technical structure’ of musical works, not as an end but as a means to an end?
[11] It is not possible to answer this question within the scope of a brief essay, for there is such a wide variety of new musicological offerings that any attempt to establish its analytical program as a unified and coherent project is bound to be defeated even before it has begun. Nevertheless, it is worth noting that note-by-note analysis has so far not played a central role in the new musicology. To avoid analysis or close reading of scores altogether may be one way of escaping the dilemmas associated with analysis as a modernist pursuit. But my interest here is not in those publications that deliberately avoid analysis but in those that use analysis, however tangentially, to buttress their claims. Here, a curious picture emerges. Rather than develop new methods for analysis, methods that are free of conventional biases, new musicologists often fall back on conventional methods. The props of insight-formation are considered self-evident. Rarely are the perceptual and conceptual foundations of musical analysis openly confronted. It is hard to square this particular manifestation of reticence among some new musicologists with the searching, no-nonsense spirit of post-modern inquiry.(12)
[12] One brief example may help to focus the issues. Susan McClary attempts to tease out “narrative agendas” in the first movement of Brahms’s Third Symphony.(13) Her aim is not to provide a detailed analysis in the manner of an “austere” formalist (like Carl Dahlhaus) but to remind us that the conventions upon which Brahms depended were not free of social meaning. Tonality, for example, involves the chanelling of desire, while sonata form is gendered in its thematic process. How are these (historically and socio-culturally) prior characterizations domesticated in the Brahms’s movement? McClary offers not one but several competing narratives, narratives that do not invest heavily in the ‘technical structure’ (in Adorno’s sense) of the movement. The first and most obvious is a gendered discourse: a heroic and obviously masculine first theme in the tonic, F major, is followed by a seductive and feminine second theme in the (unconventional) key of A major. In the development section, the second theme precedes the first, its character now changed from feminine to masculine; the first theme, which appears towards the close of the development, is now feminized. The recapitulation “goes through the paces of the exposition once again.” In this first narrative, then, McClary is interested in the character of themes, privileging overarching characterizations over inherent contradictions among the constituent dimensional processes.
[13] The second narrative is oedipal. The relationship of alterity
between first and second themes is now reread as “the archetypal
struggle of the rebellious son against the conventional Law of the
Father.” A third narrative is a racial discourse arising from the
seductive second theme, described by Hermann Kretzschmar as “Delilah.”
McClary takes this to be a sign of “Oriental exoticism,” chides the
doubting modern listener for forgetting that the theme “would have
been conceived and perceived as ‘Oriental’ within the codes of that
time,” and implies that Brahms, like the hundreds of culprits
assembled in Edward Said’s book Orientalism, was an orientalist.
(He was not the only one, of course; orientalism
forms a kind of
epistemological constant, perhaps even a cognitive constant in
European constructions of subjectivity).(14) The fourth narrative
concerns the interplay between a generalized set of norms and Brahms’s
specific practice. It turns out that the heroic first theme,
alternatively described as masculine and as embodying the oedipal
Father, is in fact “dissonant with respect to the conventions that
sustain [the movement’s] narrative procedures.” In other words the
masculine Father is atypical, an aberration. From this follows a
fifth claim, namely that the “real dilemma” of the movement is “how to
define closure in a piece in F major that insists on maintaining a
defiant
[14] This last claim may come as a surprise to some readers, for it
opens up a line of inquiry that might have formed not the end but the
beginning of a ‘formalist’ analysis. And it is here that the theorist
may wonder whether it is possible to press the earlier narratives into
the detail of the music? Can an analysis that is concerned not only
with the A–
[15] And so we reach an impasse: theory-based analysis, which prides itself on leading the analyst to the ‘truth content’ of a work as mediated by its ‘technical structure’ (Adorno), which allows the musical mind to engage directly with the compositional elements themselves—such analysis seems to be of limited utility in a project that interprets music as social discourse. The truth seems to be that new musicologists have so far not found a use for the surplus of detail that theory-based analysis produces. It would be helpful if this surplus was acknowledged either as a presence or as a problem. To object that theory-based analysis is a self-fulfilling and self-referential exercise is to pretend that tautology and circularity are ever avoidable in the criticism of art—they are not. And the analyst’s failure to reach for an extramusical label, her failure to provide a ‘translation’ of the analysis, as if that which goes unlabelled or untranslated necessarily lies outside the bounds of ‘social discourse’: these (and other) issues need to be aired.
[16] Referring generally to ‘new musicologists’—as I have done in the foregoing paragraphs—and drawing conclusions about their approach to analysis produces a limited and perhaps ambiguous set of results. By the same token, however, the habit of some new musicologists of ritually denouncing ‘formalist’ analysis would gain greater credibility if the group of theorists, too, was understood not as a monolithic group espousing a single doctrine but as a highly diverse group motivated by a few shared concerns. We could go further. Within the discipline of theory, there exists a vast range of innovative inquiries that have been overlooked by new musicologists. Were it not for theorists’ reticence about adopting new slogans, these initiatives would easily converge into a “New Theory.” New musicologists’ failure to acknowledge this work does not, of course, deny it a place in the discourses of the musical sciences. It only testifies to a willed amnesia on their part, a necessary strategy, perhaps, for redrawing the boundaries of the musical disciplines.(15)
[17] Allow me to mention, by way of conclusion, a few contributions that touch upon aspects of the new musicological agenda. In doing so, I am conscious of the scores of studies that will necessarily go unmentioned. (An attempt to include European precedents for these [mostly American] discourses alone would fill an entire paper). I am also conscious of the fact that some of my authors have moved on from the intellectual positions espoused in these papers. Nor do I mean to hold these up necessarily as the best or most influential or most representative work produced by music theorists recently. I mean simply to note their existence. Such an exercise will have achieved its aim if it encourages new musicologists to temper their proclamation of the novelty of their efforts with some acknowledgment of the traces that exist in some corners of American music theory.(16)
[18] Back in the 1970s, Thomas Clifton was busy developing ideas about the phenomenology of music, elaborating notions of play, and composing a poetics of musical silence. I haven’t seen Clifton’s name (or, for that matter, those of latter-day phenomenologists) in the new musicology’s footnotes.(17) David Lewin, in his relentless and disciplined pursuit of the ‘truth content’ of musical works, has frequently developed hermeneutic readings from paths as diverse as those of a layered metrical and hyper-metrical coherence, or the paths of voices in adjacent chromatic collections. The resulting analyses, valued for their technical demonstration as well as for their aesthetic implications, can hardly be consigned to a class of formalist analyses.(18)
[19] Charles J. Smith, writing about harmony, probably the least translatable of musical dimensions, and one that has (therefore) not featured prominently in recent readings of music as social text, encourages us to multiply our descriptions of chordal affiliation in order to embrace the challenge of multiple meaning without at the same time stooping to an all-pervasive relativism. Smith’s is not merely a call; it includes a concrete demonstration, an exploration of limits, allowing the reader to assess the limitations of his claims.(19) Alan Street has continued to remind us of the foundational instability of our terms, the contingency of our analyses, and the fragility of our conceptual constructs.(20) In 1987 Robert Snarrenberg experimented with the Derridean notion of differance in an analysis of Brahms’s Intermezzo, Op. 118 No. 2. Explicating notions of difference and deferring, Snarrenberg sought to mediate between a ‘strong reading’ of the Intermezzo following the methods of Lerdahl and Jackendoff and Brahms’s sly cadential practice.(21) Later in the same journal, Patrick McCreless gave serious attention to three of the five codes assembled by Roland Barthes’s in S/Z, testing their musical applicability on the tonal grounds of the first movement of Beethoven’s ‘Ghost Trio.’(22) Readings like Snarrenberg’s and McCreless’ allow a more effective assessment of the usefulness of transferring literary-critical terms into music analysis.
[20] Even the so-called obsession with unity has been rethought in productive ways. Rick Cohn and Doug Dempster have explored the possibility of plural unities, a concept that may at first sight appear anathema to card-carrying theorists, who have often depended on an undivided first principle. In pursuing the possible ‘divisions’ of that first principle, Cohn and Dempster are responding to a quite specific challenge, and doing so constructively and from within the discipline. It is hard to finish their article and still maintain that theory is somehow laboring under the yoke of uninterrogated foundationalist premises.(23)
[21] In a challenging and controversial article, Richard Littlefield and David Neumeyer laid bare an aspect of Schenkerian ideology, arguing that mastery of narrative tropes by the analyst is what allows the analyzed work to be configured as an aesthetic object of high or low standing, and not necessarily anything inherent in the work itself.(24) In different but complementary ways, Kevin Korsyn and Joseph Straus have appropriated Bloomian notions of anxiety of influence to explain striking recompositional points of contact between Brahms and Chopin (and Reger) and between the canonical early-twentieth century masters and their forbears.(25) In the area of musical semiotics, David Lidov, in a series of writings that deserves to be better known, has exemplified processes of meaning formation stemming from repetition, including the place of the body in the play of music’s signifiers. Again, I am yet to see a reference to Lidov’s provocative work in any of the new musicological writing.(26) Ongoing work on metaphor and on the discourses of music theory and analysis by, among others, Marion Guck and Fred Maus, continues to remind us of the constructedness of our pedagogical schemes, their situatedness, their gendered biases, and hence their limitations.(27) And Carl Schachter concluded a recent study of harmony and voice-leading in a Bach Prelude by attaching ideas of structure to ideas of theological symbolism.(28)
[22] This list could be greatly extended, of course, but not here. The evidence of these and numerous other studies ought to do three things: first, to remind us that some of the challenges posed by new musicologists have not gone unobserved in the theoretical literature; second, to help counter the gross and surprisingly popular criticism of music theory as a merely formalist enterprise and to enjoin new musicologists to approach the intellectual capital of music theory with a bit more discrimination; third, to demand of new musicologists a new and improved approach to analysis, one that escapes the dangers of present practices that they have identified. Theorists’ commitment to analytical demonstration is sometimes facilely dismissed as an outgrowth of a modernist impulse. And their acceptance of a burden of proof would seem to slow them down, throwing a ‘conservative’ veil over their activities. Why this should be a cause for concern is not clear. Academic discourse is surely not racing towards a single finishing line.
Kofi Agawu
Yale University
Music Department
P.O. Box 298310
New Haven, CT 06520-8310
kagawu@minerva.cis.yale.edu
Footnotes
1. Arnold Whittall, “Analysis.” In The New Oxford Companion to Music (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1983), vol. 1, page 58. Three years earlier, Ian Bent had defined analysis in remarkably similar
terms: “the resolution of musical structure into relatively simpler
constituent elements, and the investigation of the functions of those
elements within that structure.” (“Analysis,” in The New Grove
Dictionary of Music and Musicians, ed. Stanley Sadie [London:
Macmillan, 1980], vol. 1, pages 340–88). This procedure of first
determining the ‘units’ of a given structure and second establishing
their rules of combination is associated with musical semiology in its
earliest phases, that is, in the writings of Nicolas Ruwet and
Jean-Jacques Nattiez. See Ruwet, “Methods of Analysis in Musicology,”
Music Analysis 6 (1987), pages 11–36 and Nattiez, “Varese’s
‘Density 21.5’: A Study in Semiological Analysis,” Music Analysis 1 (1982),
pages 243–340. 1. I wish to thank Floyd K. Grave for reading both
articles and
offering illuminating comments on the intricacies of Handel’s G-minor
Sarabande, which I discuss in the course of this study.
Return to text
2. T. W. Adorno, “On the Problem of Musical
Analysis,” Music
Analysis 1 (1982), pages 169–187.
Return to text
3. Pieter van den Toorn, “A Response to Richard
Taruskin’s ‘A Myth of the Twentieth Century,’” Music Theory Online 1.5. See also his
recent Music, Politics and the Academy (Berkeley: The University
of California Press, 1995).
Return to text
4. Bent, Analysis, page 6.
Return to text
5. Kerman, “How We Got into Analysis, and How to Get
Out,” Critical Inquiry 7 (1980), pages 311–331.
Return to text
6. Kerman, Contemplating Music (Cambridge: Harvard
University Press, 1985).
Return to text
7. One could interpret Timothy L. Jackson’s “Aspects of
Sexuality and
Structure in the Later Symphonies of Tchaikovsky,” Music Analysis
14
(1995), pages 3–25 as an example of such re-attachment.
Return to text
8. Ellen Rosand, “The Musicology of the
Present,” American
Musicological Society Newsletter 25 (1995), pages 10–15.
Return to text
9. For a comment on pluralism, see my “Music Analysis
and the Politics
of Methodological Pluralism,” Revista de Musicologia 16 (1993),
pages 399–406.
Return to text
10. Lawrence Kramer, “The Musicology of the
Future,” Repercussions 1
(1992), pages 5–18.
Return to text
11. Kramer, “The Musicology of the Future,” page 5. In
his most recent
book,Classical Music and Postmodern knowledge (Berkeley:
University
of California Press, 1995), Kramer develops this vision further,
stressing the need to reinject a human interest into music criticism
and to recover a (lost) public discourse about music.
Return to text
12. It has always seemed odd to me that the on-going
debates within
theory and analysis, which in many ways capture the spirit of
post-modern inquiry, have been marginalized in the characterization of
theorists as ‘formalists.’ For one among many examples of theory’s
self-reflexivity, see the first section, “Metatheory and Methodology,”
in Perspectives on Contemporary Music Theory, ed. Benjamin
Boretz
and Edward T. Cone (New York: Norton, 1972). For an insightful and
cogent account of the historical development of music theory in the
United States, see Patrick McCreless, “Rethinking Contemporary Music
Theory.” In State of the Art: Refiguring Music Studies in the
1980s,
edited by David Schwarz and Anahid Kassabian (University of Virginia
Press, forthcoming).
Return to text
13. Susan McClary, “Narrative Agendas in ‘Absolute’
Music: Identity
and Difference in Brahms’s Third Symphony.” In Musicology and
Difference: Gender and Sexuality in Music Scholarship, edited by
Ruth
Solie (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1993), 326–44.
Return to text
14. Edward Said,Orientalism (New York: Pantheon,
1978). On
orientalism in music, see Ralph P. Locke, “Reflections on Orientalism
in Opera and Musical Theater,” Opera Quarterly 10 (1993–94),
pages 49–64. and “Constructing the Oriental ‘Other,’: Saint Saens’s
Samson et Dalila,” Cambridge Opera Journal 3 (1991), pages 261–302.
The argument is, of course, easier to make with regard to opera than
it is to instrumental music, McClary’s subject.
Return to text
15. A startling omission from the new musicology’s
discursive
practices is any sustained engagement with the intellectual heritage
of the discipline of ethnomusicology. Practically all of the new
musicology’s favorite subjects—concerns with race, gender, sexuality,
non-canonical repertoires, the nature of representation, etc—have not
only been touched upon but in some cases theorized explicitly by
ethnomusicologists. Surely this engagement is long overdue.
Return to text
16. I do not include here pockets of ‘old’
musicological research that
deal directly or indirectly with the new musicology’s concerns, but
that, too, have been relegated to the margins.
Return to text
17. Thomas Clifton’s major work Music as Heard: A
Study in Applied Phenomenology (New Haven: Yale University Press,
1983), seeks to
ground music theory in experience and to define and exemplify music
analysis dynamically in terms of acts and actions rather than static
objects.
Return to text
18. David Lewin, “Auf dem Flusse: Image and Background
in a Schubert
Song.” In Schubert: Critical and Analytical Studies, edited by
Walter Frisch (Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press, 1986),
pages 126–52, “Some Notes on Analyzing Wagner: The Ring and Parsifal,”
19th-Century Music 16 (1992), pages 49–58, andMusical Form and
Transformation: Four Analytic Essays. (New Haven: Yale University
Press, 1993). The more formal presentation of notions of networks is
in Lewin’s Generalized Musical Intervals and Transformations.
New
Haven: Yale University Press, 1987.
Return to text
19. Charles J. Smith, “The Functional Extravagance of
Chromatic Chords,” Music Theory Spectrum 8 (1986), pages 94–139.
Return to text
20. Alan Street, “Superior Myths, Dogmatic Allegories:
The Resistance
to Musical Unity,” Music Analysis 8 (1989), pages 77–123.
Return to text
21. Robert Snarrenberg, “The Play of Differance:
Brahms’s
Intermezzo Op. 118, No. 2,” In Theory Only 10 (1987), pages 1–25.
See
also the response by Robert J. Samuels in In Theory Only 11
(1989),
pages 45–58.
Return to text
22. Patrick McCreless, “Roland Barthes’s S/Z
from a Musical Point
of View,” In Theory Only 10 (1988), pages 1–30.
Return to text
23. Richard Cohn and Douglas Dempster, “Hierarchical
Unity, Plural
Unities: Toward a Reconciliation.” In Disciplining Music: Musicology
and its Canons, edited by Catherine Bergeron and Philip Bohlman
(Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1992), pages 156–81.
Return to text
24. Richard Littlefield and David Neumeyer, “Rewriting
Schenker:
Narrative – History – Ideology,” Music Theory Spectrum 14 (1992),
pages 38–65.
Return to text
25. Kevin Korsyn, “Towards a New Poetics of Musical
Influence,” Music Analysis 10 (1991), pages 3–72; Joseph N.
Straus, Remaking the Past:
Musical Modernism and the Influence of the Tonal Tradition
(Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1990).
Return to text
26. See David Lidov, On Musical Phrase.
Monographies de
semiologie et d’analyses musicales, no. 1, Groupe de recherches en
semiologie musicale, Universite de Montreal and “Mind and
Body in Music,” Semiotica 66 (1987), pages 69–97, among numerous
publications.
Return to text
27. Marion A. Guck, “Rehabilitating the Incorrigible.”
In Theory, Analysis and Meaning, edited by Anthony Pople
(Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1994), pages 57–73; Fred Everett Maus, “Masculine
Discourse in Music Theory,” Perspectives of New Music 31 (1993),
pages 264–93.
Return to text
28. Carl Schachter, “The submerged Urlinie: The Prelude
from Bach’s
Suite No. 4 for Violoncello Solo,” Current Musicology 56 (1994),
pages 54–71.
Return to text
Copyright Statement
Copyright © 1996 by the Society for Music Theory. All rights reserved.
[1] Copyrights for individual items published in Music Theory Online (MTO) are held by their authors. Items appearing in MTO may be saved and stored in electronic or paper form, and may be shared among individuals for purposes of scholarly research or discussion, but may not be republished in any form, electronic or print, without prior, written permission from the author(s), and advance notification of the editors of MTO.
[2] Any redistributed form of items published in MTO must include the following information in a form appropriate to the medium in which the items are to appear:
This item appeared in Music Theory Online in [VOLUME #, ISSUE #] on [DAY/MONTH/YEAR]. It was authored by [FULL NAME, EMAIL ADDRESS], with whose written permission it is reprinted here.
[3] Libraries may archive issues of MTO in electronic or paper form for public access so long as each issue is stored in its entirety, and no access fee is charged. Exceptions to these requirements must be approved in writing by the editors of MTO, who will act in accordance with the decisions of the Society for Music Theory.
This document and all portions thereof are protected by U.S. and international copyright laws. Material contained herein may be copied and/or distributed for research purposes only.
Prepared by Lee A. Rothfarb, General Editor and Tahirih Motazedian, Editorial Assistant