Diatonic ficta revisited: Josquin’s Ave Maria in Context
Margaret Bent
REFERENCE: ../mto.96.2.5/mto.96.2.5.wibberley.html
KEYWORDS: Wibberley, counterpoint, ficta, diatonic, accidentals, mode, notation, hexachords, Josquin, Obrecht
ABSTRACT: Roger Wibberley in MTO 2.5 has criticized a version I published of the sequence from Josquin’sAve Maria, on grounds that it flouts Glarean’s modal classification. Cristle Collins Judd has already challenged Wibberley’s construction of mode, and I further deny Glarean’s relevance on chronological grounds. The first part of my article restates and revises some of the premises (ignored by Wibberley) which provided the context for my discussion of the Josquin piece; the second part extends my original discussion of that passage, and offers some comments and questions in response to Wibberley’s paper.
Copyright © 1996 Society for Music Theory
A mind is like a parachute. It only works if it is open.
[1] I am grateful to Roger Wibberley and other correspondents following his article in MTO(1) for airing some important questions and providing me with an incentive for this reply. I do plan eventually to produce a more fully revised and corrected expansion of the thesis I set out in “Diatonic ficta” (henceforth DF),(2) incorporating replies to Karol Berger and Peter Urquhart, but this may serve as a partial, interim statement.(3)
[2] Cristle Collins Judd began her posting of July 23 to mto-talk (“Wibberley, MTO 2.5,” mto-talk 23 July 1996) by addressing not so much Wibberley’s solution but his modal premises. In order to restore premises rather than symptoms to the centre of the discussion, I shall first set the Josquin aside. Since some readers may not be familiar with DF and the context in which I used that example, and since none will be able to infer it correctly from Wibberley’s article, it might be helpful if I now restate and amplify some parts (only) of the thesis particularly germane to this discussion, and take this opportunity to adjust some areas where my presentation may have proved incomplete or too elliptical.
[3] Since I invoke counterpoint so strongly, I had better explain the specific sense in which I use the term. Counterpoint, as defined in DF from Tinctoris and earlier theorists, is concerned not with lines or vague general attributes but with two-voice progressions—what we might call two-part or dyadic harmony.(4) At least up to the late 15th century, the handling of more than two parts was treated by theorists as an extension of those dyadic principles. It is in respecting and reconciling melodic principles and the rules of counterpoint that ficta is necessitated; I have tried to show that ficta needs to be viewed in the context of counterpoint as a whole, and not informed just by precepts specifically labelled as ficta. The list discussion has referred to the need to set priorities in cases of conflicting principles (Judd, 23 July: “the challenge to Bent’s solution of the passage in question comes not from modal theory, but in relation to how one interprets horizontal and vertical priorities in determining ficta.” Just so.). I did indeed attempt(5) to draw from theorists a set of primary guidelines for applying contrapuntal precepts (melodic and “harmonic”) precisely with a view to setting priorities when those precepts come into conflict, though there is still a long way to go in spelling out qualifications, exceptions and licences to those primary considerations, some of which have been addressed by Berger and Urquhart.
[4] A fundamental difference between renaissance notation and ours is that, then, “not to notate accidentals is not to misnotate the music.” Notated accidentals were truly accidental. No more or less importance attaches to their prescriptive power or indeed to their absence than would, say, to that of sporadic fingerings in some early keyboard sources. We may be glad of help, however occasional or eccentric, but notation should not be viewed as incomplete or inaccurate when lacking such accidental indications. When we transcribe old music into a notation in which accidentals have become essential, we tend to read the notation thus transcribed as a stronger default than it ever could have been, one from which “deviations” have to be justified and to which accidentals have to be added, or notes inflected. It is we, not they, who “add accidentals,” depart from the notation, and make inflections. They had no term to distinguish our F flat from F: if a note was F according to the clef, it was still “F,” even F fa ut, even if it had become our “F flat” by local contrapuntal operations. This is what I shall mean by the term “contrapuntal descent” (see [8]), as distinct from a descent caused by tuning.
[5] It is the modern transcription that has traditionally been treated as our default, as when we refer to “the notation as it stands,” or at “face value,” despite changing standards in editorial practice. After considerable editorial experience, it is now my conviction that so to treat it is a greater disfigurement and source of misprision than to start from the other end, as I now advocate. It is obvious that their starting point for these determinations, their access to the music, was not from a modern transcription but rather through singing from their manuscripts and prints. Early notation provided a weak intervallic default organization by clef and signature, but because it was incompletely prescriptive of pitch (hence “weak default”), the performer expected to arrive at actual sounds by some means besides prescriptive notation. Modes and hexachords (see [18] below), while very important for other purposes, run on separate tracks from each other and are at best marginally relevant to the realization of counterpoint and the determination of ficta. The most important key to successful realization of weakly prescriptive notation is to complement it as they must have done, armed with an approximation of the elementary training shared by composers and singers, and which composers presumed in their singers when they committed their compositions to notation, namely, for these purposes, practical training in counterpoint. Taken in partnership, notation and counterpoint create a more strongly prescriptive basis for realization. Like them, we should develop the (for us very different) musical skills that are dictated by singing from the original, acquiring an awareness of the constraints and freedoms inherent in the notation, as well as a sense of the violence done by putting weak-default (early) notation (without the complement of a strengthening counterpoint training) into a (modern) form that demands to be read by the standards of modern notation as a “strong” default. DF grew out of a recognition that the answers to many of these questions follow naturally from the experience of reading and singing from original notation instead of from conceptually different modern translations. If this is a counsel of perfection, we need at least to learn (by doing it) to simulate that experience so that in using modern scores we can make all allowance for their inherent distortions, as one glimpses the original language through the shortcomings of a translation. It is those earlier habits that (echoing Crocker 1962) we need to recover, by reading their books (musical and theoretical) rather than ours, by observing what they don’t say as well as what they do.
[6] Armed with the rudiments of mensural and contrapuntal skills (correct realization of perfect simultaneities and cadential approaches in discant-tenor pairs, and perfection of melodic 4ths and 5ths unless prevented), one reads one’s own part in a state of readiness to re-interpret, of readiness to change one’s expectation of how to read the under-prescriptive notation (not to change the notation!) in prompt reaction to what one hears. The “default” of the line you see, together with the melodic articulations you expect to apply (perfecting linear fourths, making cadential semitones) is controlled and sometimes over-ruled by the counterpoint you hear. The “default” that is “changed” is not the notation as transcribed, but the expectation of how the original notation is to be realized.(6) Once the new (i.e. old) habits of listening and adjusting aurally have been internalized, most solutions follow naturally, and almost never require the lengthy discussions that arise when singing from transcribed score. I fear that I am now as skeptical of the authority of assertions about what is and is not possible in early polyphony, from those who have not acquired fluency in reading in this way, as I would be reluctant to accept literary correction from someone who read a language only in translation. The weak default of under- prescriptive notation becomes a strong default when coupled with contrapuntal training, but it is a different strong default from modern, mostly white-note, notation “as it stands,” and the inherent status accorded accidentals by current editorial conventions.
[7] We are still free to treat results so obtained as a default that can or must be departed from, but this default is as different as it could be from that of a modern transcription. We will approach their thinking and musicianship more closely by trying to do it their way (the Kon-Tiki principle of testing whether the expedition is possible using the original equipment), even if the results turn out to be very different from what we have grown used to by doing it from the opposite, unquestionably anachronistic direction, and even if we then decided (on grounds yet to be determined, since “modal fidelity,” pace Wibberley, will no longer do) that the new results need further adjustments of a different kind.
[8] Our musical culture has raised the definition of
frequency and pitch-class to a high status, for analysis,
editing and performance. My reading of a range of early
theorists leads me to posit a slightly fuzzier status both
for what we would call pitch-class and for frequency, a
status that places pitch closer to the more flexible view
of durations and tempo that we still have. This reading
rests partly on conspicuous circumlocutions and the late
arrival of precise language, notation and measurement,
partly on a pervasive Pythagorean mentality expressed in
the tuning system, partly on my understanding of
counterpoint and the internal evidence of some paradigmatic
pieces, not the Josquin. We routinely make rhythmic and
durational analyses on the basis of notated values even
though we know that performance fluctuations, some
necessary, some elective, expected but elusive to precise
definition, are ignored by the analyst. We are not
necessarily shocked if an analysis disregards the fact that
a piece, any piece, may end slower than it began. A
terminal ritardando needn’t affect certain kinds of
analysis; nor need the ritardando of pitch caused by a
logical downward sequential spiral (Obrecht) shock us. I do
not assume, as Wibberley seems to impute [2], that for the
“Obrecht piece to begin on F and end on
[9] Nor need such a spiral impinge on, pace Wibberley, a modal analysis. The work by Powers and Judd on Aaron’s modal assignations(7) makes it clear that Aaron in the Trattato was indeed making those assignations “on paper,” in such a way as to permit two startlingly different-sounding pieces (such as Mon mari m’a diffame by De Orto and E la la la by Ninot le Petit, nos. 12 and 27 in Canti B) to receive the same classification. (How, for example, does Wibberley deal with such witness or advocacy of mode?) This is closer in time to Josquin than Glareanus and should restrain Wibberley’s construction of the relevance of (his perception of Glarean’s view of) mode to the sound (= contrapuntal realization) of a piece. The relatively higher status we now accord to sounding pitch definition is reflected in the facts that we (not they) have made accidentals essential, and that we fix frequency and pitch class much more sharply than we do metronomic values. Pitch, in short, has a higher status for us than rhythm. Skilled singers of course would be aware of changes, both at the micro-level of tuning, shifting commas of intonation, and at the macro- level of occasional contrapuntal spiralling sequences such as I believe to be indisputable in the Willaert and unavoidable in the Obrecht examples.
[10] Berger (in Musica ficta) was unwilling to accept the evolution of his “renaissance” view of a keyboard-like repertory of available pitches from my free-standing, vocally-conceived, Pythagorean, pre-keyboard “medieval” view of pitch, tuning and vocal counterpoint. Indeed, he (like Wibberley) is reluctant to accept any possibility of fluctuation, by tuning or counterpoint, and there we differ. I believe that Berger’s view is broadly valid for a later period and with different qualifications from those to which he applies it, and that it can at some point be reconciled with mine, though not as a background to music before 1500, where I judge it to be anachronistic. I wrote: “Musica recta is not an arsenal of fixed pitches but denotes a set of relationships to a notional norm of pitch stability that is more like a flotilla at anchor than a Procrustean bed or a pre-tuned keyboard. The ‘operation of musica ficta’, that is, the substitution at any point, for contrapuntal reasons, of a tone for a semitone (or vice versa), could mean that the absolute frequency of the As, Bs, Cs that follow may not be the same as they were before, although the local interval relationships of small segments will remain intact. The taking of a conjuncta (substitution of a tone for a semitone or vice versa) anywhere in the system may change the actual pitches following that point, without changing the relationships except at that point. The value of a semibreve may be changed by proportional operation or mensural change; the contextual relationships of that semibreve will continue to be observed after the point of change even if the absolute durations represented by the same symbol in the same context are different from before. Both for mensuration and for pitch, the values are achieved through local context and without reference to long-term absolutes.” (DF p. 10, and passim.) Especially since the Powers-Judd illumination of renaissance views of mode, it has yet to be shown that there is any basis other than modern prejudice for claiming such absolutes with respect to sounding pitch, as distinct from notated status, for a musicianship that was not yet, before the 16th century, bound by keyboard-like reference. It is the notion of frequency volatility of both these kinds that has already educed the loudest howls of protest (e.g. from Berger, p. 45). This is a genuine point of disagreement, much more fundamental than the Josquin example. That singers were aware of these shifts does not prove (again, pace Wibberley and Berger) that they would have found them undesirable or striven to avoid them. Before about 1500, and often afterwards, there is nothing to constrain a piece to a fixed frequency or, in certain special circumstances, to a fixed constancy irrespective of tuning, for a letter-name-plus-hexachord syllable point on the gamut; these fixities are what I see as coming in with the rise of the keyboard as instrument of practical and theoretical reference. They would have been as ready, I believe (as we are not), to redefine a frequency or, as in the Willaert, to adopt a changed but logically-approached pitch for E, as to accept (as we can without special pleading) a new value for a semibreve beat after a proportional shift, whether specified or otherwise necessitated.
[11] Diatonic (and hence also chromatic) status was
defined melodically in the 16th century and earlier.(8)
The presence of sharps and flats does not necessarily
render music chromatic; diatonic status then, as later, is
not confined to “white notes.” F–
[12] I have read with interest the mto-talk postings of Nicolaus Meeus on tuning and intonation (“Wibberley, MTO 2.5,” mto-talk 19 August 1996, mto-talk 26 August 1996). He rightly surmises that I believe some kind of just intonation (with pure 5ths and 8ves) applied to a cappella vocal counterpoint “with pure intonation, Pythagorean in principle [Meeus and Lindley also use this qualification], but probably with justly tempered thirds in practice” (DF p. 18). However, Meeus’s view of tuning is so clearly anchored to a sophisticated keyboard-equivalent that, in setting a standard of reference for a piece or a passage, it comes at the discussion from the opposite direction from mine. As for adjustments on dissonances, the frequent pitch redefinitions that result from a Pythagorean approach (as I understand it; see next para.) result in no bumps, no audible local dislocations.
[13] It is highly significant that there was no standard starting point for tuning the Pythagorean monochord. In DF I presented Pythagorean tuning as the antithesis of keyboard reference: “even if two monochords were tuned with true Pythagorean ratios, their resulting frequencies could be slightly different if those ratios were applied from a unison by a different route through the spiral of fifths.” (See DF, especially 3–7.) The monochord was unsuitable as an accompanying instrument; apart from very elementary pedagogic use, it was a representation of Pythagorean ratios rather than a proto-keyboard for an individual performance; this of course allows for the kind of disciplined frequency movement I believe to be endemic to their thinking, hence the Pythagorean spiral, not circle, of fifths. The monochord represented the proportions that yielded those sounds, but in practice (by pure 5/4 thirds) may have been on a slightly different track from them (separate tracks, yet again). I believe that the view of a constantly redefining Pythagorean application overcomes the rejection (by Meeus, mto-talk 26 August, and implicitly by many others) of Pythagorean tuning throughout the very period where it is prevalent, and the point of theoretical reference for proportions of all kinds. Indeed, the better in tune a performance sounds in terms of its local progressions (with pure thirds and fifths), the more likely it is to move down, as several professional performers confirm. It is a short step from here to believe, as I do, that Pythagorean intonation was constantly redefinable around new central notes in the course of a piece. The arrival on each new true fifth sonority would then be the new point of departure for purposes of tuning calculations, thus achieving local perfection and a smooth, gradual descent by comma increments. This rules out a notional keyboard standard for performance; any performance with a keyboard necessitated compromises, a fact that exercised several 16th-century theorists. The final sequence of a piece like Absalom, in which (I believe) pure (Pythagorean) fifths would, ideally at least, have been mediated by pure 3rds (5/4) which in turn anchor the next pure fifths of the sequence, is almost bound to end at a fractionally lower frequency unless it is (artificially, and irrelevantly for this discussion) disciplined by adherence to a pre-tuned keyboard standard or repertory of available pitches (Berger’s view).
[14] If you believe, with Lowinsky, that frequency must have been constant, a musical absolute (as if to be accompanied on equal-tempered or fretted instruments), then obviously pieces such as the Willaert duo and Greiter’s Fortuna can be regarded, as he did, as precocious manifestos for equal temperament.(10) He was prepared to accept contrapuntal descent under certain conditions, but not frequency descent. By contrapuntal descent, I mean pieces like the Obrecht and Willaert examples (see DF) and the Greiter where even with constant frequency the “F” at the end is, by purely contrapuntal spiralling, one or more semitones lower than the “F” at the beginning. If you believe, with me, that (1) such logical contrapuntal and melodic descent through the spiral of fifths in these pieces is inherently Pythagorean in concept and (2) that Pythagorean tuning of 5ths in practice, with pure 3rds (5/4), was predisposed to result in comma slippage, pieces which thus descend contrapuntally can be construed as (in these cases, late) manifestos of Pythagorean conception and execution, as posited above. Rejection of any degree of frequency volatility obviously makes it harder to overcome resistance to contrapuntal descent, despite the existence of pieces (Willaert, Greiter) where all are agreed that it must happen. Otherwise, the tuning consideration need not be an impediment to considering other premises of this argument (notably contrapuntal correction) independently of a specific tuning system.(11)
[15] Now for a confessional review of some miscalculations in DF, and a further unpacking of some ellipses. First, it was misleading to present my examples in modern score. I should never have expected readers to accept, even hypothetically, a paradigm shift that emphasizes the radical difference between old and new notation while at the same time transcribing the examples in such a way as to imply that they are equivalent, and exposing them to all the shock of unfamiliarity, and to conceptually foreign analyses of their tonality and tuning. As I put it, “neglect of some primary musical facts has led us to tolerate the aural dissonance of intolerable intervals before we accept the merely graphic dissonance of an intolerable-looking modern score.” (DF p. 48.) My examples in DF should, rather, be seen as “phonetic” approximations, into a different language, of what might be sung from the original, or might be at least the first default so derived. But it is hard to know what else to do. It is unrealistic to assume that readers will have the training or time to get together to sing examples from parts, the counsel of perfection spelled out above, thus simulating the process by which contrapuntal training was applied to notated music, but modern scores might at least be read with that awareness.
[16] Since DF I’ve had the benefit of reading and discussing recent developments in work on mode, especially by Powers and Judd, and I would now reformulate some of what I said about mode in the light of that, though the basic disconnection, on which Judd and I agree, is not much affected. For the moment, I will confine myself to quoting her clear statements to the mto-talk discussion: (23 July) “there is simply no need for mode or ficta to impinge one upon the other because they occupy different conceptual and theoretical realms,” and, after quoting Wibberley’s “Only by this means [retaining some diminished fifths in performance] would it have been possible to remain faithful to the mode on account of the actual notes Josquin composed in the particular combination chosen by him,” Judd continues: Wibberley’s “conclusion is based on a modern understanding of mode as tonal system. Nowhere is such a view articulated by Glarean. Such a view fundamentally misrepresents the very nature of musica ficta in seeking to fix pitches in a way that Renaissance musicians clearly did not. Although Bent’s solution is not one that I would adopt for this passage, there is nothing in the Glarean passage quoted by Wibberley in para. 9 to argue against it. Wibberley is imputing to Glarean an ‘internal’ view of the modes, but nothing in Bent’s solution changes the final or range (i.e. the external criteria by which the mode is recognized), hence Bent’s view that her solution does not disturb ‘modal coherence.’”
[17] While I do not think that I am “mixing up”(12) performance and understanding, I do see that this is something that needs to be addressed, and one way in which I hope to advance the formulations of DF is to make that distinction a bit clearer. I hope I have done so by introducing the “default” element into paras [4–7] above. Having advocated even more separation of tracks than I did in DF, I see that here I have not gone far enough, and that certain rare conundrum passages like the Josquin that are capable of a perfect contrapuntal realization might in practice not receive it. Just as there might be a reading of a piece that was perfectly consonant with the traditional (Wibberley’s) modal-scalar ideal, but a reading that one would not choose in practice, so there may be passages like the Josquin sequence where the perfection of the counterpoint would have been tempered in practice. This is where my discussion above of a “default” concept may be helpful. While I in no way withdraw from “my” version of the Josquin as an exercise in contrapuntal perfection, I am perfectly prepared to accept the possibility of a more cautious compromise (see below), if only to direct attention to the premises by admitting that they need not stand or fall by an “extreme” example. I chose examples that would make vivid the radically different conceptual underpinnings of old and new notation, rather than to illustrate the much subtler consequences that this understanding brings in practice for most “normal” pieces; but if we can now agree to recognise the Josquin as a special case, the way may be open for broader acceptance of what I have outlined above.
[18] In an attempt to set out the main tributaries of a proposed radical shift in understanding the basis of notation (not necessarily or always entailing a shift in the sounding results), I inevitably overstated or understated some aspects, largely by insufficiently freeing myself of some modern prejudices. In attempting to formulate the complementary nature of notation and counterpoint, I may have overstated the weakness of the default, leading others to impute a less disciplined relativism than I actually intend. I hope that the default element helps here. I seem to have understated my position on the role of hexachords and solmization, and hence misled Daniel Zager and some others about how mastery of solmization relates to ficta.(13) I never meant to claim (as Zager implies but does not state) that solmization can resolve counterpoint/ficta problems. I do not share his dependence on solmization to determine counterpoint. Rather the converse: contrapuntal decisions, once made, can be expressed in terms of solmization, the nearest they had to a precise language in which to conceptualise and name sounds. But since they stretched the system to cope with all eventualities, so that anything could be solmized by extensions and disjunctions, the criterion of easy solmization is not a valid arbiter of which sounds are or are not possible. To argue a particular solution from solmization is to let the tail wag the dog. I wrote: “Hexachords provide a functional context for semitone locations which have been predetermined by musical considerations, but they do not in themselves determine what the sounds will be. The hexachordal voces are the means by which those sounds become practically accessible in vocal polyphony, just as, by analogy, fingering is the means by which small groups of notes are physically negotiated on instruments.” Hexachordal thinking permeates their terminology. It guides us away from the notion of “inflections” of individual notes and into that of small scalar segments (sometimes projected as tangents from the scala of musica recta) that accommodate and articulate semitones, the need for which is pre-determined on contrapuntal principles. It cannot in itself solve individual ficta problems just as, conversely, no ficta solution can be rejected on grounds that it can’t be solmized. Nor, as Judd agrees, can modal theory solve ficta questions, whether Aaron’s or Glarean’s. What I have proposed is the beginnings of a system drawing simple rules and priorities from counterpoint theory, principles whose development, exceptions and qualifications will have to venture beyond the point where theory helps us and be derived in turn from actual composed music; but they can be projected homeopathically in the direction indicated by that theory (rather than antibiotically from our alien perspective), and fleshed out from a practice stripped of some modern varnish (such as the notion of modal fidelity as an arbiter of tonal stability, and of modern notation “as is”). Some of these precepts are strong and binding. Some are weaker and open to alternatives and competing priorities. All of them can be accepted without the obligation to choke down my Josquin example whole as a prescription for practice. That is negotiable.
[19] Having thus slightly rearranged the furniture to
permit (I hope) constructive discussion, now to the
Josquin. I should add to my list of miscalculations that I
ought to have saved that example until a later time, in
order not to distract attention from the premises, or at
least I should have continued the argument, which I will
now try to do. It is an exceptional puzzle, and has been
so recognized by several writers, notably by Dahlhaus, with
the rather different conclusion that “der Tonsatz abstrakt
konzipiert ist und dass sich Josquin ueber die
Unentschiedenheit, wie er zu realisieren sei, hinwegsetzte,
da sie ihm gleichgueltig war.” (“the composition is conceived
in the abstract, and that Josquin disregarded
the inconclusiveness as to how [the composition] was to be realized,
because he was indifferent to [the inconclusiveness.”) Dahlhaus thus posits
the composer’s indifference to the actual resulting
sounds, and argues that counterpoint thus abstractly
conceived may have lacked either prior aural imagination
of such sounds or, indeed, any musically acceptable
realization(14) To this view
Berger and I join in taking
exception, if for different reasons.(15) Josquin’s sequence
is a conundrum, of a fairly rare type. In the disputed
measures, he gives us not just one text-book sequential
“cliche” chain of fifths and sixths, but two superimposed
contrapuntal pairs, discant and tenor, tenor and bass(16)
both of which, (not just the upper pair, pace Wibberley [13]),
have claims to perfection and place constraints on the
other. Dahlhaus gave up on the passage. Lowinsky favoured B
natural in bar 48 because it fitted his sense of the piece
as being tonal as well as (nearly pure) Ionian.(17)
Urquhart accepts
[20] The provocation, therefore, is not mine but Josquin’s. It remains interesting and inescapable that he set up this sequential passage of two superimposed contrapuntal pairs in such a way that an intervallically flawless reading,(20) if not a perfect solution, is possible. Josquin’s conceit deserves better than that we retreat from it on anachronistic grounds based on notions of white-note supremacy or modal chastity. Wibberley has attempted to make the case for doing so on modal grounds, but for reasons given by Judd, and because of the irrelevance to Josquin’s personal arsenal of the later testimony of Glarean, let alone Zarlino, it will be clear that I do not think he has succeeded. We have to choose in practice whether to depart from that particular kind of perfection— indeed, whether Josquin was provoking us to do just that, rather than whether to depart from the notational translation of a modern score. That is the nub of the “default” aspect of my hypothesis. Bach chose occasionally to break “rules” about parallels or leading notes; we must be prepared for Josquin to do likewise, and to imply that we need to realise certain passages imperfectly. But we had better have a reason more firmly grounded in what we can discern of the musical practice of Josquin’s contemporaries than simply disliking something that differs from what we have—perhaps mistakenly—grown used to. Addled by years of hearing and seeing under-inflected performances (of the notation “as it stands”) with too many flat leading-notes and proto-tonal diminished fifths, our mistrained ears are not reliable arbiters. That “we haven’t tried it because we don’t like it” (to quote the old Guinness advertisement) is a self-fulfilling prophecy.
[21] I am pleased to see that there has come to be
acceptance of the bass
[22] Except for the bar 48
[discantus] | D | C | B |
[tenor] | F | E | D |
[bassus] | D B* | C | G |
The fifth at bar 48 on the other hand does not contract but
forms part of an ongoing sequence and must, as we seem to
agree, be perfect. But how do the following limbs of the
sequence differ in the constraints that are placed on
consonance and contrapuntal perfection? Wibberley cites Aaron in
support of his claim [15] that “None of this means,
however, that diminished fifths were to be completely
banned from composed music; it simply means that perfect
consonances did not admit them, and that where perfect
consonances were to be attained [my emphasis] such
intervals had to be eliminated.” If this chain of fifths
is not a prime, and literally text-book, candidate for
“where perfect consonances were to be attained,” I don’t
know what is. Having accepted the
[discantus] | F | E |
[2nd discantus] | B | C |
[tenor] | D | C |
But he fails to recognise that the Josquin passage does not meet those criteria, because its unique feature is that two primary and non-cadential contrapuntal progressions are superimposed, and that the upper part therefore cannot be treated as subsidiary.
[23] In light of Judd’s postings to mto-talk it is almost superfluous for me at this point to deny the relevance of Glarean’s twelve-mode system (or for that matter Zarlino’s counterpoint theory(22)) to discussion of constraints and freedoms that might have applied in Josquin’s mind and his expectations of performance. Glareanus says nothing relevant to counterpoint and ficta. His 12-mode system is no more germane to how Josquin might have classified the Ave Maria than would be a roman numeral analysis to his harmony. Wibberley would be mistaken to assume that my silence on Glareanus was for any other reason (see DF 45). Judd published a modally-based analysis of the motet, not mentioned by Wibberley;(23) in principle, her and my statements can co-exist without disagreements affecting our different approaches: “there is simply no need for mode or ficta to impinge one upon the other because they occupy different conceptual and theoretical realms”(“Wibberley, MTO 2.5,” mto-talk 23 July 1996).(24) Judd further commented in the same posting: “Wibberley’s straightforward mapping from composer to theorist (and vice versa) highlights an even more problematic issue. I find his view of theorists as ”witnesses“ difficult to sustain. Aron, Glarean, and Zarlino are, after all, advocates of their own agendas as well as witnesses.” Then Wibberley (“Wibberley, MTO 2.5,” mto-talk 19 August 1996): “The presumption underlying my article was that the Josquin motet WAS [Ionian tonality], especially since Glareanus said so.” and (“Wibberley, MTO 2.5,” mto-talk 5 August 1996): “What is clear to me is that Glareanus is telling us something quite definitely about the way the COMPOSER has composed the music, rather than about the way others might have performed it.” Does Wibberley not distinguish between subsequent comment and classification on the one hand, and what could have been in the composer’s mind, on the other? It is indeed a big leap to go from a subsequent theorist (especially Glarean) with his own axe to grind to make the assumption that because this was in his mind it must have been in Josquin’s more than 50 years earlier.
[24] Finally, some further comments and questions for Wibberley. Why is it acceptable for Absalom to “modulate” (a modern term and concept) and, as Wibberley would have it, to “remove the harmony from its base,” but not (by his standards) for the Josquin or indeed the Obrecht? By what standards does he judge such “removal” not only permissible but “very successful” while other comparable pieces are not similarly favoured?(25) Indeed, we cannot be sure exactly what Glareanus means by his “without removing the harmony from its base,”(26) invoked by Wibberley against excessive fictive adjustments. Glarean’s language and context may suggest some connection with Aaron’s distonata via and Tinctoris’s distonatio, neither of which easily lends itself to the construction Wibberley would wish to place on it. This is a difficult area, yet to be explained; Wibberley jumps too readily to the conclusion that it must mean removal from defaults of modern, not of renaissance, imposition.
[25] That Wibberley accepts some “ficta additions” (I would
prefer to call them contrapuntal adjustments) is clear in his
posting of 8 August (“Wibberley, MTO 2.5” mto-talk 8 August 1996).
Are all of these consonant with his view of mode in pieces
classified by Glareanus (or indeed Aaron), or with the way that
these theorists would have classified them? Up to what point
does he accept “inflections,” and which ones, on what criteria
and authority, and why no further? How does he reconcile the
constraint he draws from Glareanus with explicit and
incontrovertible text-book examples of ficta from the early 16th
century, such as offered by Ornithoparcus and Listenius?(27) Are
works classified by Glareanus to be given different treatment in
order that they can conform with Wibberley’s sense of what
Glarean means, irrespective of any musical characteristics that
may suggest otherwise? He also accepts ([13]) that my example is
consonant. He sometimes invokes the rules of consonance, though
he does not make it clear where he departs from the
notational-contrapuntal premises of DF—where indeed? It is on
(albeit anachronistic) modal grounds that he determines that the
rules of consonance may here be broken. Wibberley adopts the
[26] Wibberley [21] and n.11 is unclear about the status of the fourth. When the fourth appears in composition treated not as a dissonance, it is because it is not part of the primary contrapuntal pair. In this case there will be a
fifth or a third below it: | ||
[discant] | G | |
[contratenor] | D | |
[tenor] | A | G |
Another and more medieval way of explaining this would be that each of the upper parts formed a contrapuntal pair, cadencing on a 5th and 8ve respectively, with the lowest part, when that part is functionally the tenor at that moment. When the fourth occurs between the primary dyadic pair—that is what Tinctoris means by “in counterpoint”— it must be treated as a dissonance, i.e prepared and resolved. Wibberley’s citation of Tinctoris’s “Hence it is rejected [as a consonance] by counterpoint” (n.11) means just that. He misinterprets Tinctoris’s statement as meaning generally in the musical texture, but counterpoint clearly must be understood specifically here, or it doesn’t make sense, and Wibberley has to labour to do so. He confuses the issue by bringing in acoustics ([15] and n.15). Acoustic perfection is on a separate track (again!) from contrapuntal perfection. Later instructions for the behaviour of a third or fourth voice are also ancillary to the primary dyadic counterpoint.
[27] A substantial portion of Wibberley’s article [paras. 14–19]
is devoted to the examples in Aaron’s Aggiunta to his
Toscanello. I have discussed these examples and
rules,(28) and invite interested
readers to compare my
explanations with Wibberley’s for some of the features he
observes. He fails to point out [14] that Aaron’s
discussion of partial signatures relates them to mode; see
ACN p. 321. See ACN p. 324 for a discussion of Aaron’s bias
to the lowest voice. In para 18 Wibberley raises Orto’s Ave
Maria, used as an example in Aaron’s Aggiunta, and says
that the only reason for the diminished 5th in the
preceding bar is that there is a G in the bass beneath it.
Not so. The
[28] No one these days can deny the importance of language, and the way the terms we use permeate our thought-processes and prejudices. Thus it is surely also important, for our purposes, to flag dangerous short-circuits or short cuts that may symptomise inappropriate matching of concepts and terms, so that, when we have to use modern terms, we can at least be aware that the absence of an early term may be eloquent.(29) I pointed out at the beginining of DF that medieval theory had no single word for pitch or for rhythm, but rather congeries of differently-shaded words, a powerful symptom of the separate tracks on which, for example, mode, counterpoint, solmization and tuning operate. These tracks are interdependent, but not in the way we imagine when we prioritize not only pitch, but a frequency-biased notion of pitch.
[29] In conclusion:
There is still a widespread and under-supported belief that
renaissance composers must have stuck largely to “white-
note diatonicism” except where we are forced to believe
otherwise. This has been supported from modern misprisions
of mode (such as Wibberley’s), now being unpicked, that were in
turn introduced to counter what we now see as the
excessively harmonic-tonal approaches to early music by
previous generations of scholars. The unpicking of all
related assumptions still has a long way to go. Recent
repudiation of artificial shackles of “modal purity” (or
whatever we call it) invites us to start afresh with open
minds about the sound of early vocal polyphony. (The
question of tuning is separable, but obviously important,
since it is loaded with many of the same modern
assumptions. The contrapuntal arguments are not affected by
precisely what tuning system they are realized in, but can
be made on their own track.) The urgent question remains:
if Judd’s view that “modal fidelity” poses no constraints on
ficta prevails over Wibberley’s view that it does, i.e. if it is
true that “paper” modal assignations may be disconnected
from realized sounds; and if my premises outlined above
find even partial acceptance, are we not further overlaying
modern prejudices on early music by assuming that in order
to be “coherent” it must conform to our standards of
long-range tonality (and frequency)? Some of the same
questions arising from our imposition of value-laden terms
have been raised by Richard Taruskin and others for
“authenticity,” a term of approbation which admits no
alternative; I believe we must do the same for “stability”
and “coherence.”
Margaret Bent
All Souls College
Oxford, OX1 4AL
England
margaret.bent@all- souls.oxford.ac.uk
Footnotes
1. Roger Wibberley, “Josquin’s Ave Maria: Musica Ficta versus Mode,” Music Theory Online 2.5 (1996).
Return to text
2. Margaret Bent, “Diatonic ficta,” Early Music History 4 (1984), 1–48.
Return to text
3. Karol Berger, Musica ficta: Theories of Accidental
Inflections in Vocal Polyphony from Marchetto da Padova to
Gioseffo Zarlino (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1987), especially 43–8; Peter Urquhart, “Canon, Partial
Signatures, and ‘Musica Ficta’ in Works by Josquin Desprez
and his Contemporaries,” Ph.D. dissertation, Harvard, 1988;
Urquhart, “Cross-Relations by Franco-Flemish Composers after
Josquin,” Tijdschrift van de Vereniging voor Nederlandse
Muziekgeschiedenis 43 (1993), 3–41. Their paraphrases have
been invaluable in showing where my formulations need to be
strengthened.
Return to text
4. Richard Crocker, “Discant, Counterpoint and Harmony,” Journal of the American Musicological Society 15 (1962), 1–21.
Return to text
5. In DF 23–29; also in my “Accidentals, counterpoint and
notation in Aaron’s Aggiunta to the Toscanello in
Musica,” The Journal of Musicology 12 (1994), 306–344
(Festschrift issue for James Haar: Aspects of Musical
Language and Culture in the Renaissance), henceforth ACN.
See especially 324–5.
Return to text
6. See also my “Resfacta and Cantare super librum,”
Journal of the American Musicological Society 36 (1983),
371–91, and “Editing early music: the dilemma of
translation,” Early Music 22 (August 1994), 373–394.
Return to text
7. Harold Powers, “Is Mode Real? Pietro Aron, the
octenary system, and polyphony,” Basler Jahrbuch für
historische Musikpraxis XVI (1992), 9–52; Cristle Collins
Judd, “Reading Aron reading Petrucci,” Early Music History
14 (1995), 121–152.
Return to text
8. James Haar, “False Relations and Chromaticism in
Sixteenth-Century Music,” Journal of the American
Musicological Society 30 (1977), 391–418.
Return to text
9. As Wibberley, [2] and [10].
Return to text
10. E.E. Lowinsky, “Matthaeus Greiter’s Fortuna: an
Experiment in Chromaticism and in Musical Iconography,”
Musical Quarterly 42 (1956), 500–519, 43 (1957), 68–85.
Return to text
11. 11. Of course, transcriptions of these or any pieces can
be sung in equal temperament, but I disagree with Lowinsky
that they must be; indeed their spiralling and fifth-
based conception makes it most unlikely that this would
have happened in a locally well-tuned vocal performance.
Return to text
12. As Berger alleges, Musica ficta, 46. He also rebukes me for not
keeping in mind letter-plus-solmization designations, a
charge directly contradicted by DF 7–12.
Return to text
13. Daniel Zager, “From the Singer’s Point of View: A
Case Study in Hexachordal Solmization as a Guide to Musica
Recta and Musica Ficta in Fifteenth-Century Vocal Music,”
Current Musicology 43 (1987), 7–21, referred to by Wibberley.
Urquhart (p. 368) invokes awkwardness of solmization against my
version of the Josquin.
Return to text
14. Carl Dahlhaus, “Tonsystem und Kontrapunkt um 1500,”
Jahrbuch des Staatlichen Instituts für Musikforschung
preussischer Kulturbesitz 1969, ed. D. Droysen (Berlin,
1970), 7–17, especially 15–16.
Return to text
15. Berger, Musica Ficta, 166–70.
Return to text
16. I give “text-book” sources for this sequence from
Hothby and Aaron in DF 29–30.
Return to text
17. E.E. Lowinsky, Tonality and Atonality in Sixteenth-
Century Music (Berkeley and Los Angeles, 1961), 20.
Return to text
18. Urquhart discusses the Ave Maria example on pp. 368–69
of his
dissertation. His solution, couched in an often seriously
misleading report of my premises, is given in his article
cited in n.3, especially pp. 25–8, and also in a paper to
the American Musicological Society, November 1995.
Return to text
19. Wibberley states [13]: “Since it is impossible to render the
Josquin passage in any way other than that proposed by Bent
without failing to eliminate all diminished fifths
otherwise occurring between notes of the upper voices (such
an elimination being her prime motive).” I invite him to
re-read the way I set up the Josquin example. If any
fifths, by Wibberley’s criteria, are to be regarded as “where
perfect consonances were to be attained,” they are surely
these. See [22] below on diminished fifths, and [27]
on Aaron.
Return to text
20. Before someone raises it on the mto-talk discussion list,
I explain in DF (29–34) why the altus part, for internal and
diagnosable reasons, takes a low priority in this passage, and
why the sequence, as “pure” counterpoint, can be contemplated
separately. But the altus may yet be the best way into
arguments as to how one might depart from a contrapuntally
pure default.
Return to text
21. See DF n.48, where I comment on the source status of
the bass B flat. Wibberley however places it in parentheses in
“my” version, while stating: “By the accepted rules of
consonance, the bass b must be flattened to b-flat in order
to provide a perfect consonance with the tenor” (Wibberley [4]).
Return to text
22. Wibberley [29] “Josquin would seem, in the example under
consideration, to have arrived at Zarlino’s ”impasse,“ but
Bent has not followed Zarlino’s advice in finding a
suitable way around it.” Why should I have taken the advice
of a theorist 100 years later whose theoretical world,
including his use of terms like diatonic, is entirely
different from Josquin’s?
Return to text
23. “Some Problems of Pre-Baroque Analysis: an Examination
of Josquin’s Ave Maria
Return to text
24. Why, incidentally, does Wibberley so dislike Zager’s term
“modal purity” and how does it differ from his own “modal
fidelity” [13, 26]? He complains “If, by ”modal purity,“
[Zager] has in mind a succession of notes and harmonies that
arise only from the pure diatonic notes of a particular
scale,” but in his own n.8 Wibberley refers to “the use of notes
outside the diatonic notes of that mode.”
Return to text
25. Wibberley, mto-talk 5 August. His reference to this as a
“powerful rhetorical device” suggests that he might be
following Lowinsky in demanding extra-musical reasons for
what they both call “modulations,” a position that can lead
to great inconsistencies of treatment between musically
similar constructions. Consider the arcane lengths to which
Lowinsky went to defend his Secret Chromatic sheep against
the musically similar goats who did not qualify by virtue
of their texts. See also DF n.47. (NB the Absalom
“modulation” is not dependent on notated accidentals and
would have to occur, even without them, as in the Willaert
and Obrecht pieces.)
Return to text
26. I plead innocent to the mind-boggling charges packed
into sentences such as Wibberley’s [10]: “The whole point of
Margaret Bent’s solution is that the harmony is, via the
‘necessary’ application of diatonic ficta, ‘removed from
its base.’” And I don’t know what Wibberley means by claiming [7]
that I see “modal coherence as a close relative of pitch
stability,” citing DF 45–47, where I wrote: “Modal theory
does deal with some kind of long-term tonal coherence, but
not necessarily such as can be equated with pitch
stability—another distinction that has lost its force for
us.” There are numerous examples in Wibberley of discourteously
careless reporting, not only of my alleged views but also
Bonnie Blackburn’s, astoundingly misrepresented.
Return to text
27. These and others are cited in E.E. Lowinsky, “Secret
Chromatic Art Re-examined,” Perspectives in Musicology ed.
B. Brook et al. (New York, 1972), 91–135.
Return to text
28. DF 19, ACN (see n.5); for Aaron see also Judd’s
article in n.7.
Return to text
29. In view of his reproaches to me for anachronism, I’m
surprised to see Wibberley use terms such as root (n.16),
tonicization (n.7) and modulation [10].
Return to text
Copyright Statement
Copyright © 1996 by the Society for Music Theory. All rights reserved.
[1] Copyrights for individual items published in Music Theory Online (MTO) are held by their authors. Items appearing in MTO may be saved and stored in electronic or paper form, and may be shared among individuals for purposes of scholarly research or discussion, but may not be republished in any form, electronic or print, without prior, written permission from the author(s), and advance notification of the editors of MTO.
[2] Any redistributed form of items published in MTO must include the following information in a form appropriate to the medium in which the items are to appear:
This item appeared in Music Theory Online in [VOLUME #, ISSUE #] on [DAY/MONTH/YEAR]. It was authored by [FULL NAME, EMAIL ADDRESS], with whose written permission it is reprinted here.
[3] Libraries may archive issues of MTO in electronic or paper form for public access so long as each issue is stored in its entirety, and no access fee is charged. Exceptions to these requirements must be approved in writing by the editors of MTO, who will act in accordance with the decisions of the Society for Music Theory.
This document and all portions thereof are protected by U.S. and international copyright laws. Material contained herein may be copied and/or distributed for research purposes only.
Prepared by Lee A. Rothfarb, General Editor and Tahirih Motazedian, Editorial Assistant