|
||||||||
|
Volume 11, Number 4, October 2005
Copyright � 2005 Society for Music Theory
Luis-Manuel Garcia*On and On: Repetition as Process and Pleasure in Electronic Dance Music |
KEYWORDS: Electronic Dance Music, repetition, pleasure, listening
ABSTRACT: Repetition has often been cast in a negative light, associated with immature or regressive states. This view is reflected in music criticism and pedagogy, recast in aesthetic terms and it also reappears in cultural criticism, attacking repetition as a dangerous tool for social control. Defenses that have been mounted in favor of repetition seem inadequate in that they tend to recategorize certain repetitive practices as not-quite-repetition, rather than defend repetition tout court. This article uses examples from Electronic Dance Music (EDM) to provide an alternate approach to repetition that focuses on the experience of pleasure instead of a static attribution of aesthetic or ethical value. In particular, this is explored through three concepts: repetition as process, repetition as prolongation of pleasure, and process itself as pleasurable. Underlying these concepts is a formulation of pleasure first coined as Funktionslust, or "function pleasure," reconceived here as "process pleasure."
Received October 2005
[1] "I LIKE THE TUNE, BUT IT'S SO REPETITIVE."(1)
[1.1] Why does this sentence make intuitive sense, even though the adjective
"repetitive" has no modifier indicating a positive or negative evaluation? Much
like adjectives such as "monotonous," "boring," and "unoriginal," "repetitive"
seems to come with a negative connotation built-in. Outside the realm of
aesthetic criticism, however, repetitiveness can play seemingly positive roles.
For example, it is central to memory formation as well as to redundant
error-checking in data transfer protocols, and it plays a large role in
pedagogy, childhood development, and pattern recognition in general.(2) This
connection to childhood learning, however, has at times worked against
repetition, associating it with childlike behavior, underdeveloped
consciousness, and regression.
[1.2] Returning to the humanities and social sciences, this interplay of
developmental necessity and psychopathology surfaces in discourse as anything
from unease to suspicion to outright hostility and, in turn, many attempts to
rehabilitate repetition read like an apology or an awkward change of subject. It
is my intention here to offer another rehabilitation--or, rather, a
reevaluation--of repetition, which reads neither as apology nor sidestep. Rather
than ponder whether repetition can be good and/or beautiful, I will focus on how
repetition can generate pleasure--a question of performance and practice rather
than ontology. To illustrate these practices of pleasurable repetition, I will
turn to a number of musical examples taken from a genre most explicitly
associated with repetitiveness: Electronic Dance Music (hereafter: EDM).
[2] THE REPUTATION OF REPETITION
[2.1] The reputation of repetition in various disciplines and discourses is far
more complex than I had first let on; this complexity requires a return to
history before moving on with my own theorizing. My work responds to the
contributions of many previous writers and it will be easier to explicate my own
positions after having reviewed those of other prominent figures in discourses
on repetition. I use the plural form of discourse here because, as will soon
become apparent, there are several discursive streams that address repetition,
not all of which are in constant dialogue with the others. This discursive
diversity, along with the broad scope of a concept such as repetition, makes a
comprehensive and exhaustive recounting next to impossible; the following review
is therefore necessarily selective and merely serves to briefly historicize
repetition.
[2.2] Although I intend to foreground practice and experience in this paper,
most discourse on repetition in the past has been keenly ontological. One
salient exception to this trend is the work of Benjamin in his consideration of
art and reproduction. In his essay, he argues that the aura of authenticity
attached to a work of art is destroyed or liquidated when it can be easily and
precisely reproduced. He argues that "authenticity is outside
technical...reproducibility" and thus it is dependent on the failure of
technology.(3) (As a side note: this puts an interesting spin on post-digital or
'glitch' music, where failing technology is part of the aesthetic.) From the
perspective of a Marxist critique of cultural value, the liquidation of
authenticity--or, rather, bourgeois authenticity--is not necessarily negative,
and his stance on repetition is correspondingly ambiguous.
[2.3] Admittedly, Benjamin and I are not frying the same proverbial fish. He is
more concerned with the duplication of complete works and the impact that has on
their exchange value, while I am more concerned with repetition internal to
musical performances and their aesthetic value. Nonetheless--if I can run with
the metaphor--these fish swim in the same pond; the fields of inquiry overlap
and writers publishing in spaces closer to mine have drawn on his arguments.
Moreover, they often rely on an active re-interpretation (misreading?) of his
argument: the threat to authenticity is no longer the repeatable artwork, but
the repeating one (and the stakes appear to run beyond authenticity).
[2.4] After Benjamin, one of the most often cited and recited critiques of
repetition comes from the realm of psychology and psychoanalysis. The work of
developmental psychologists often considers repetition as a learning behavior
essential to childhood development. However, this has become a liability for
repetition as some writers have made this connection into a rigid one-to-one
mapping. Proceeding from this logic, repetition is only suited for didactic
situations; in any other context it becomes childish, immature and regressive.
This idea is perhaps best summarized in a quote by Susan McClary, who is
paraphrasing Adorno paraphrasing Schoenberg interpreting Freud: "if we
understand a piece of music as an allegory of personal development, then any
reiteration registers as regression--as a failure or even a refusal to keep up
the unending struggle for continual growth demanded for successful
self-actualization".(4)
[2.5] This particular chain of writers is quite apt, as Schoenberg's writings on repetition seem to be informed at some level by Freud's interpretation of repetitive behavior; in turn, Adorno seems to take his view of musical repetition from Schoenberg and that of the psychological implications from Freud. Although the foregoing quote from McClary neatly summarizes his most widely circulated position, I shall trace Freud's work on both pleasure and repetition in some detail. This is not only because many of the scholars mentioned below draw on his work, but also because I will be drawing on the work of one of his contemporary critics for a model of repetition and pleasure in the following section (see [3.3]).
[2.6] Although Freud's theories are often dealt with as a synchronic whole, they in fact developed and changed over time; for our purposes, the most important of these changes was the "turning of 1920".(5) Before writing Beyond the Pleasure Principle, Freud had believed that all human behavior could be explained by the "pleasure principle": that all actions were set in motion by an initial "unpleasurable tension" and that these actions tended toward relaxing this tension through a production of pleasure or a reduction of unpleasure.(6) In this book, however, Freud rejected this as too simplistic; it did not explain why humans sometimes subjected themselves to unpleasure--whether voluntarily or compulsively. He then added a second principle, the "reality principle": the postponement of immediate pleasure (or the toleration of immediate unpleasure) as a step towards a more distant and indirect pleasure. However, this principle did not explain what Freud called "repetition compulsion," which came from the observation of repetitive children's games such as Fort-Da (similar to "Peek-a-boo"). Freud rejected the theory that such games aimed at a mastery over the mother's absence, instead preferring a mastery of a different kind. By his interpretation, repetition was related to an ego instinct that sought to restore an earlier state of inertia--a pre-organic state of stillness that can only be truly fulfilled in death. Freud named this instinct Thanatos, the death instinct, against which he also erected its antagonist Eros, the life instinct; this division of instincts came to replace his previous ego/sexual division. It was this connection between repetition and the death instinct that enabled Freud to explain why some of his patients felt compelled to repeat past traumas in their current lives (i.e. repetition compulsion). The "regressive" or "retrograde" character that Freud saw in the death instinct made repetition not a process of psychological development, but the mark of an immature or underdeveloped ego.(7)
[2.7] Apparently drawing on Freud, Schoenberg often depicts his ideal listener as a 'wakeful and trained' mind; one that has no wish to be insulted by having the same musical idea presented to him repeatedly.(8) However, Schoenberg also acknowledges in Die Grundlagen der musikalischen Komposition that "comprehensibility in music seems to be impossible without repetition".(9) As Andreas Jacob has noted in his paper on this issue, Schoenberg displays a certain unease or conflictedness with regards to repetition most likely arising from this collision of philosophical ideals and compositional practicalities.(10)
[2.8] While Schoenberg's concerns about repetition resided mostly in its effect on the individual listener, Adorno also placed repetition in the broader context of culture (industry) and society. Although Adorno's commentary on repetition is scattered among his writings and somewhat inchoate we can organize them around issues of standardization and regression. Generally speaking, Adorno's standardization-critiques tended to focus (like Benjamin) on the repetition of entire art objects, while his regression-critiques tended to focus on repetition as a formal, intra-opus process. Adorno identifies a process of standardization in repetitive cultural forms through a twofold mapping of (capitalist) industrial production and marketing onto artistic production: part interchangeability (or modular design) and pseudo-individuality.(11) This latter term refers to the superficial details of a commodity, such as racing stripes on a car, that cause a consumer to prefer one over the other, even though they are essentially identical. In one instance, Adorno provides an example of how the culture industry enforces standardization and passive listening by using repetition to create a feeling of recognition, which eventually transmutes into the acceptance of a cultural object that would have otherwise been rejected.(12) Continuing in this same vein, Adorno critiques "traditional" art music for its repetitive use of *topoi* (part-interchangeability), which composers covered with a patina of variation (pseudo-individuality).(13) In this same passage, Adorno imagines the driving force behind such compositional standardization to be a stubborn, "regressive repetition," which leads us to Adorno's second set of criticisms against repetition.
[2.9] As the term "regressive repetition" implies, Adorno's notion of repetition as regression is informed by a Freudian psychoanalytic tradition. Although this regression sometimes seemed to imply a reactionary view of history as circular and thus foreclosing on rupture and revolution,(14) his lengthier use of repetition as regression in his critique of Stravinsky's work is psychoanalytically inflected.(15) This psychoanalytic register is reinforced by the other vocabulary he uses to critique Stravinsky: catatonia, hebephrenia, infantilism, psychosis, fetishism, depersonalization, dissociation. Indeed, it appears that Adorno's strategy was to throw the entire psychoanalytic arsenal at Stravinsky's music, in the hope that something would stick; the result of this strategy is that each psychopathological term (including regressive repetition) appears briefly and without a great deal of elaboration on how he understands these disorders to work.
[2.10] In addition to Adorno's explicit reasons, Ingrid Monson suggests that his own life experiences under the burgeoning Third Reich might have led to a more immediate and emotional response to repetition. Perhaps he associated musical repetition with the rhythms of marching, and thus with militarism and fascism?(16) While I like the idea that Adorno was, indeed, a human with his own share of fears and neuroses, I do not think that his view of repetition arises purely from transference. In other words, we should not dismiss Adorno's critique simply because his tone of voice sometimes approaches panic. Rather, the explanatory power of Adorno's critiques rest on two points:
[2.11] As we will soon see, this view of collectivity runs counter to those
frequently found in anthropology and ethnomusicology. Nonetheless, Adorno's
arguments are still used to great effect in popular music criticism, often
employed by popular music critics themselves. Phrases such as "It's all just the
same song over and over," or "It's not songwriting anymore, just studio
production," echo these same Adornian critiques and fears of industrialization
and mass mediation.
[2.12] To a greater degree than the preceding discursive streams of cultural
studies, critical theory and art criticism, music theory and analysis have
historically aimed for objectivity, tending to avoid evaluative claims. While
this statement is less tenable now as the landscape of theory changes, the
ethical and evaluative questions asked of repetition still tend to be avoided in
this field in favor of descriptive typologies.(18) Despite this overt avoidance
of value statements, these typologies still offer some cultural commentary, even
if indirectly. For example, Rebecca Leydon's typology of minimalist tropes
includes six very interpretive types: Maternal, Mantric, Kinetic, Totalitarian,
Motoric and Aphasic. While limits of space (and time) preclude a closer
examination of these categories, it is worth noting that, according to Leydon's
explication, most of these terms rely on an allegorical connection between
repetition as a loss of musical syntax, and repetition as a loss of the musical
subject (imagined here as the listener).(19) Since, in a postmodern context, the
loss of the subject may not necessarily be a failure, her view is not as
explicitly negative as that of others. Repetition remains a loss, however: a
destructive rather than generative force.
[2.13] Nonetheless, this emphasis on how repetition works rather than what it is
or how valuable it is informs my own intended focus on practice and performance
rather than ontology. Although I still intend to address issues of politics and
cultural value, music theory's focus on process is crucial to an effective
reevaluation of repetition. Also crucial to this reevaluation is a consideration
of more positive perspectives on repetition--views that can contrast the
pessimistic and suspicious tone of much of the foregoing discourse.
Ethnomusicology, through its anthropological lens, has provided some of the most
cogent arguments for repetition, especially in the study of African and
African-Diasporic expressive culture.
[2.14] John Miller Chernoff's 1979 examination of West African music-making
provides one of the earliest comprehensive explorations of repetition to be
published under the ethnomusicological banner. He takes a largely optimistic
approach, arguing that repetition allows for a more participatory mode of
music-making and, in turn, that the interlocking layers of West African
percussion use repetition to 'lock' its participants into a musical
instantiation of social relationships.(20) Like Adorno, Chernoff sees
collectivity in repetitive music, but instead maps this to a more benign
communitas, whence individuality can arise without being alienated. This
positive spin on participation has been furthered by the work of Charles Keil
most notably, whose notion of 'participatory discrepancies' relies on the
ability of individuals to make personalized but compatible contributions to a
communal, egalitarian groove.(21)
[2.15] This homology between musical structure and social structure is a common trope in ethnomusicology, and it is not without its weaknesses. Steven Feld's essay, entitled "Sound Structure as Social Structure," considers how the relatively egalitarian and classless features of Kaluli society may find resonance and rearticulation in their musical practice. While his argumentation remains largely in favor of this structural homology, he does address inequalities in both social and musical practice largely revolving around gender.(22) Ingrid Monson points this out when she uses the example of James Brown's band to show how a seemingly egalitarian musical practice nonetheless involves a division of labor and a corresponding division of power, money and prestige.(23) Thus two useful insights can be taken from ethnomusicology:
[2.16] From the earliest reports of the colonial encounter, rhythm and repetition have had a racial valence, doing "work" as a difference-making calculus of ethnic and racial others. It is little surprise, then, that questions of repetition surface frequently in studies of the African diaspora. This is especially appropriate for this literature review, which precedes an engagement with examples of Electronic Dance Music, since the African diaspora has played a significant role in the development of EDM genres. Disco emerged in the 60s and 70s in New York at predominantly black and Puerto Rican gay clubs as a mix of gospel, R&B and funk. Similarly, predominantly black, Puerto-Rican and gay communities served as crucibles for early house (Chicago), garage (New York) and techno (Detroit). It is with particular interest, then, that I turn to Veit Erlmann's contribution to Monson's book on the African diaspora. In an essay that lies somewhere between ethnomusicology and popular music studies, Erlmann uses the commonly-assumed connection of repetition to black expressive culture to bring up the concept of Signifyin(g).(24) Using Henry Louis Gates's formulation as a starting point,(25) Erlmann defines Signifyin(g) as a discursive strategy common in nearly all African-diasporic expressive culture. This strategy entails the use, reuse and misuse of pre-existing cultural forms and artifacts in contexts that often bring out ironic, unexpected or subversive meanings. Erlmann goes on to suggest that, in the context of Signifyin(g), repetition foregrounds style and manner over the presentation of novel content. Thus, if the communication of content is not a priority, Rebecca Leydon's mapping of loss of musical syntax to a loss of the musical subject does not hold for musics of the African Diaspora. As Erlmann argues, repetition does not aim at a reflection of reality, but a ritualization of reality.(26)
[2.17] However, Erlmann's interpretation of how repetition functions has not--to
my knowledge--been taken up in the mainstream of popular music
studies/criticism. Contributions from popular music discourses have generally
fallen into both positive and negative categories. For the most part, those
popular music scholars who do directly address repetition either rearticulate
Adorno's critiques or lionize repetition by characterizing repetitive music as
essentially transgressive and oppositional. In this latter case, repetitive
music is radicalized as the mortal enemy of the dominant discourse of Western
art music, heroically disrupting narrative and denying meaning. In this manner,
one might map repetition to cultural rebellion and social rupture. However, the
same could be argued for radically disjunct and abstract non-repetitive music,
and certainly not all production of repetitive music occurs in oppositional,
transgressive contexts. A great many things may offend narrowly imagined notions
of Western art music traditions, and thus repetition gains no special
distinction in this respect.
[2.18] Richard Middleton, in his essay on repetition and popular music, touches
upon an important issue for Electronic Dance Music. He considers Kiparski's
continuum of variability and formula for oral poetry, encompassing three
categories on this continuum, from 'fixed' to 'flexible' to 'free', where
'fixed' represents the most repetitive and unvaried forms.(27) Kiparski then
correlates the two extremes of this continuum to a parallel continuum of
function from 'ritual' to 'entertainment.' Middleton suggests a corresponding
musical continuum, with disco at one end and Jimi Hendrix at the other.(28)
Although he stops just short of raising the issue, he nonetheless provides a
path to identifying an underlying evaluation of unvaried repetition that reduces
it to a purely functional and non-aesthetic object. Following from his example,
disco as the "entertainment" end of the spectrum risks being dismissed as merely
a soundtrack for an oft-derided and primitivized ritual of sexual sociality.
This point has also been made with regards to Electronic Dance Music in the work
of Mark Butler.(29)
[2.19] Middleton also tries to explain the seemingly common-sense criticisms of repetition in popular music, even from within popular music discourses. Phrases such as "It's all the same" make sense because of a slippage in evaluative logic. There is an implied and/or ideological sense in which "a particular conventionalized proportion of repetition to non-repetition is naturalized".(30) Consequently, popular music is often judged to exceed this proportion and thus to be in bad taste.
[2.20] This line of thought brings me to the essay that essentially started this whole project: Russel Potter's defense of black cultural forms with regards to repetition.(31) Entitled "Not the Same," Potter clearly resents what he considers a racial essentialism connecting black expressive culture to repetition. He takes Tricia Rose to task for her monograph, Black Noise,(32) accusing her of just this sort of essentialism, then proceeds to argue that the repetition so prominent in black-influenced popular music is not really repetition. He bases his defense on the distinction between blank repetition and repetition with difference--that is, Signifyin(g). However, he establishes this distinction by shifting Middleton's conventional boundary of acceptable repetition to a position that rescues jazz, blues and rap, but at the expense of disco, techno and other dance music genres. The problem with Signifyin(g) as a defense for repetition is that it relies on the continuing devaluation of it's own Other: exact duplication or repetition tout court.
[2.21] It is these last two issues that not only inform, but also motivate my work on repetition. As I had mentioned in my introduction, defenses of repetition tend to apologize or sidestep the issue altogether. Those that sidestep do so by reducing repetition to pure function, describing how repetition functions without addressing meaning or value. Those that apologize do so by defending their own localized practice of repetition at the expense of repetition as a larger concept--often identifying another genre as unacceptably repetitive in a sort of sacrificial substitution. Also, although the detractors of repetition tend to be too cynical and pessimistic, its defenders in cultural studies such as Deleuze and Lyotard, often place their discourses at a great remove from musical practice.(33) In the "pan-media" approach of cultural studies, music tends to get passed over for careful analysis, and thus cultural theorists often fail to ground their argumentation in the analysis or close reading of cultural (musical) artifacts--an aporia that I shall begin to fill in the second section of this essay.
[3] THEORIZING PLEASURE IN AND OF REPETITION
[3.1] The choice of Electronic Dance Music (EDM hereafter) to illustrate the
process and pleasure of repetition seemed perfectly obvious to me at the
beginning of the research process. Not only did I see EDM as the most
unapologetically repetitive of popular music meta-genres, but its electronic
mediation seemed to fulfill Benjamin's prophecy that, "To an ever greater degree
the work of art reproduced becomes the work of art designed for
reproducibility".(34)
[3.2] Nevertheless, there remains some groundwork to take care of before I can
proceed to issues of pleasure and repetition in EDM. In particular, I need to
address the ontology of pleasure itself, as well as seek out a theory for the
engendering and experience of pleasure that is compatible with repetition. To
this end, I would like to return to Freud's theories of pleasure and repetition
and also introduce an alternate and dissenting voice. In my view, there are two
main problems underlying Freud's conception of pleasure (and, consequently,
repetition compulsion): the a priori pathology of repetition and the failure
to imagine pleasure arising from something other than satiation. This first
issue is relatively straightforward; for Freud, repetition was always already
pathological. Being grounded in a clinical discourse, Freud was interested in
explaining a phenomenon (repetition compulsion) that he already knew to be
harmful. Thus his task was not to question its positive or negative effects, but
to explicate why and how some of his subjects repeated past traumas.
[3.3] As a "positive" theory of repetition and pleasure, then, Freud's notion of
repetition compulsion (and its connections to the death instinct) is already a
non-starter. It remains, however, as a "negative" or critical interpretation; in
other words, it does not comprehend repetition and repetitive behaviors in their
totality, but identifies potential problems. Freud's categories of both pleasure
and repetition are thus too narrow, which possibly explains why he found that
the latter was "beyond" the former. Writing only seven years after Freud's
Beyond the Pleasure Principle, Karl Bühler strongly criticized Freud's
interpretation of pleasure and repetition compulsion, suggesting that Freud's
connection of repetitive children's games to a death instinct reflected the
despair of Schopenhauer's pessimism.(35) In the place of Thanatos and a return
to primordial stillness, Bühler proposes a tripartite system of pleasure:
satiation pleasure (Lust der Befriedigung), function pleasure
(Funktionslust), and the pleasure of creative mastery (Shaffensfreude, Schaffenslust, Schöpferfreude).(36) The first of these terms, satiation
pleasure, Bühler considers to be the only form of pleasure that Freud
recognizes: desire is engendered by drives or the recognition of a lack,
pleasure is generated by (incompletely) fulfilling it. Given that Bühler's word
for satiation (Befriedigung) can mean both "fulfillment" and "pacification,"
one can imagine that Freud's interpretive move to "death" was not so distant.
Notably, satiation pleasure places the subject in a receptive, passive position;
however much one actively seeks it out, fulfillment is always partially
dependent on circumstance. Also, satiation pleasure is committed to a teleology
(desire-->pursuit/anticipation-->satiation-->desire?), which makes the
temporality of pleasure arising from satiation uncertain: how long does pleasure
last during and after fulfillment? To give a musical example, if one considers
the audition of an arch-form piece, how long does pleasure last after the
climactic Höhepunkt? How long does the memory of climactic fulfillment
generate pleasure?
[3.4] In contrast to satiation pleasure, function pleasure arises from process itself, rather than the process's results. In this case, the subject is in an active position, not merely pursuing but generating his/her own pleasure. Again in contrast to satiation pleasure, function pleasure is coextensive with the activity that generates it, guaranteeing that pleasure continues at least as long as one is engaged in the process. A paradigmatic example would be that function pleasure arises from baking a cake (provided, of course, that one enjoys baking), while satiation pleasure arises from eating it. However, this example is somewhat misleading in that it implies that one form of pleasure necessarily precedes and results in another one--function pleasure is simply "bonus" pleasure awarded to one who actively pursues his/her own satiation. My understanding of function pleasure, however, extends also to activities that do not necessarily produce desire-fulfilling objects, such as dance and musical performance,(37) and thus function pleasure arises properly from process. For this reason, I would like to replace the term "function"--which unhelpfully implies teleology and production--with "process pleasure." The distinction between production pleasure and Bühler's third category of pleasure arising from "creative mastery" is less clear, and those who have followed Bühler have generally collapsed this last category into the preceding one: the experience of creative mastery is what generates Funktionslust--the pleasure of a job well done.(38) However, I would like to retain this division and redraw the bounding line between these categories in a new fashion. Changing the more cumbersome "pleasure of creative mastery" to "creation pleasure," I would see the difference between creation pleasure and process pleasure as a matter of productivity: the first arises from the satisfaction of productive achievement, while the latter arises from activity itself. If satiation pleasure arises from receiving and creation pleasure arises from making, process pleasure arises from doing.(39) Also, I would like to borrow the notion of "mastery" from Bühler's third category to help explain how "doing" can itself generate pleasure. Much like the pleasure of creative mastery arises from a task/product well done, the pleasure in process arises from doing well--mastery over an activity and the objects involved in it. Dancing, for example, is an opportunity to take pleasure in manifesting capacity, control and proficiency in dance as an activity and over the body as its medium.
[3.5] Before tracing my way back to repetition, I should provide some
clarification and a few caveats. Bühler and his theoretical inheritors were
clearly interested in promoting their versions of process pleasure and creation
pleasure as non-pathological, healthy paths to pleasure. I am not as interested
in promoting one form of pleasure over the other; I can easily envision
"positive" and "negative" instances of each category. Neither do I wish to
suggest that process is naturally or necessarily pleasurable; as any survivor of
severe obsessive-compulsive disorder will attest, process is by no means
pleasurable if one cannot stop. As we will soon see, I also do not view these
categories of pleasure as operating independently from one another.
Nevertheless, I will be paying greater attention to process pleasure because it
is the most difficult to explain, the most difficult to justify and--as a
strange form of pleasure that neither consumes (satiation) nor produces
(creation)--offers the most potential for novel explications of pleasure.
[3.6] It is also through process pleasure that I see a connection back to
repetition. As Bühler argues, in response to Freud, repetition is not beyond the
pleasure principle, but a prime bearer of process pleasure.(40) As I will argue
below, repetition functions as a sort of process, structuring activity in a
manner that optimizes opportunities to exercise mastery of listening/dancing.
[3.7] In addition to issues of pleasure, EDM presents some challenges with respect to previous theories of repetition. In particular, Keil's notion of 'participatory discrepancies' relies on live, communal performances where an individual's contributions can vary from moment to moment and in contrast to other individuals. While this ethos of communality and communitas can still be imagined through the interplay of dancers and DJ, the degree to which this is 'live' in the same manner as Keil's examples makes it difficult to draw close parallels. Nonetheless, this particular challenge also makes the case of EDM especially appropriate for this paper. Since I intend to avoid defending one form of repetition by imagining a more repetitive Other form of repetition, EDM's potential to repeat with digital precision will force me to deal with repetition in its most problematic form, much in the same way that Linda Williams' seminal work on pornography passes over the less objectionable "soft" porn and "couples films" and focuses directly on hard-core and BDSM forms of pornography.(41)
[3.8] Similar motivations also inform my choice of examples from the styles and sub-genres within EDM. The three tracks(42) from which the following examples will be drawn are not a representative cross-section of EDM, but rather a sampling of those sub-genres that make the most explicit and extended use of repetition. In particular, these three tracks will represent two sub-genres of techno (itself only one genre/category within the realm of EDM): its more austere branch of "minimal" techno, and tech-house, which is a hybrid of house and techno styles.(43)
[3.9] To aid in this consideration of repetition--particularly that of practice rather than ontology--I would like to make a shift away from the term 'repetition'. Following Christopher Hasty's notion of meter as process, Eugene Montague has forwarded the concept of repetition as an ongoing and open process, which he identifies with the gerundive form, 'repeating'.(44) Within the context of EDM, I will parallel this formulation by employing the noun 'loop' and the gerund 'looping.' These terms come from two complementary sources: Mark Spicer's recent article on accumulative form, and Mark Butler's work on rhythm and meter in EDM. Spicer defines accumulative form as the "technique of building up a groove gradually from its constituent parts".(45) In turn, he defines 'groove' as "a tapestry of riffs", and defines 'riffs' as atomic musical ideas that normally repeat. This is the point of contact with my notion of loops and looping. Effectively, loops are riffs of modular length that one strongly expects to repeat, and looping is the practice of layering, adding and subtracting loops, allowing for the seemingly paradoxical effect of an ever-changing same.(46)
[3.10] This notion gains support from Mark Butler, who defines the loop as the fundamental unit of musical structure for EDM.(47) Also, he underlines the importance of looping by arguing that cyclical repetition, and thus repeated listening, allows for the perceptual separation of EDM's complex timbral and rhythmic layers.(48) To further this, I would also add that my notion of looping in EDM as an ongoing and open process is crucial to an understanding of a musical genre that is not normally recorded in a visual form of notation. Thus, the structural perception of EDM tracks and sets almost always occurs over time, with a fading memory of past events and a growing expectation of future ones.
[4] LOOPING AS PROCESS
[4.1] I would like to begin with this idea of looping as an open process and
explore how this is manifested in EDM. This is best approached through Mark
Spicer's recent work on accumulative form. Spicer begins from Peter J.
Burkholder's analysis of Charles Ives' work, wherein Burkholder defines
'cumulative form' as Ives' idiosyncratic practice of reversing the order of
thematic development.(49) Rather
than present a theme or idea and then proceed to fragment and develop it, a
'cumulative' work gradually presents thematic fragments, which then, as Spicer
puts it, "crystallize into a full-fledged presentation of the main theme in a
climactic pay-off at the end of the piece".(50)
Spicer modifies this idea in his definition of 'accumulative form,' replacing
the climactic presentation of the main theme with the climactic
accumulation of riffs into a texturally thick groove.
[4.2] I believe that Spicer's version of accumulative form (substituting loops for riffs in this case) is one of the most widely used prototypical forms in EDM, and I did not need to look far to find examples. The first track that we will consider is an especially clear but exceedingly extended example, so I can offer only fragments from various points in this accumulative process. The recording is a track entitled "ethnik," taken from the 1994 'minimal' techno album musik by Plastikman, also known as Richie Hawtin.(51)
[4.3] In the partial transcription that I have provided (Figure 1
[PDF]), one can find
a graphic representation of this accumulative form in the accumulation of layers
over time; what I could not convey with this transcription is the corresponding
accumulation of intensity, although I hope it will be clearly audible in the
audio excerpts provided. The three audio excerpts show the process of
accumulation at three points: Excerpt A shows the slow fading in of a
rhythmically flexible flute line over a metrically ambiguous bassline; B is both
a local accumulative climax and the midpoint in the larger accumulation towards
C. All three of these excerpts also show differing ways of employing looping to
articulate a point or period of change, and make use of the common expectation
in EDM that structural changes occur on multiples of 4--whether four beats, four
bars, eight bars or more. Excerpt A (Audio 1A) fades in a 4-bar flute line
gradually, so that it is not at first clear when the loop started and thus when
one can expect another change in texture. B (Audio 1B) makes use of a similar
strategy with a loop of congas, which makes the sudden appearance of the
three-part drum loop surprising but all the more emphatic as a structural
downbeat. On the other hand, C (Audio 1C) forecasts its high point of
accumulation by applying an EQ filter-shift to the drum loop--marked by a shift
in shades of gray--then removing the triangle loop four bars beforehand and the
drum loop one bar beforehand.
[4.4] In a fashion similar to that of Plastikman/Hawtin, many EDM producers do
not only employ accumulative form, but also provide a vocabulary of aural
signposts to signal various stages of arrival or accumulation. The introduction
of the kick drum, the sudden removal of several layers only to return with more
force, and the play of metric ambiguity all provide listeners of EDM with aural
cues. I will defer issues of process pleasure until our final example (see [6]),
but I would like to take a moment to consider how the experience of
mastery--which provides the ground for process pleasure--works in looping as
process. These aural cues and signposts optimize EDM for listening mastery; they
provide opportunities for listeners to insert themselves into the looping
process and manifest their proficiency with these massive hypermetrical
structures. Although it is difficult to generalize, listeners can and often do
take these opportunities to manifest their mastery in physical ways--whether by
marking points of accumulation with punctuating gestures (hand claps, shouts,
"drops", spins, etc.) and changes of dancing style, or by finding ways to bodily
articulate the processes of looping, demonstrating their capacity to grasp and
"ride" the loop.
[5] LOOPING AS PROLONGATION OF PLEASURE
[5.1] Before continuing to a consideration of looping-as-process as pleasure, I
would like to explore how pleasure may arise from looping outside the operation
of pre-determined structure. As I had mentioned earlier, Mark Butler has
proposed that the precise and extended repetition idiomatic to EDM benefits the
listener in allowing him or her to perceptually separate textural layers. Butler
further developed this idea in his paper read at the 2003 annual meeting of the
Society for Music Theory (Madison, WI), wherein he suggests that the use of
unresolved grouping dissonances in EDM does not necessarily pose an irresolvable
perceptual problem for the listener.(52) Instead, he forwards a mode of
listening whereby a listener can shift focus between dissonant layers, granting
perceptual primacy to one grouping at one moment, and to another at the next.
[5.2] I think that this begins to explain how the repetition of seemingly short
musical units can generate pleasure over extended periods. Using my taxonomy of
pleasures, this aspect of looping provides a sort of creation pleasure grounded
in the creation of process. A persistently-looping, dense collection of riffs
provides a dense layering of textures without pre-determining the listener's
path of focus. In this manner, a listener is able to construct his/her own
process(es) of attention, creating a unique sonic pathway and manifesting a form
of mastery over the ordering of these looping elements. This contingent and
improvised process is then made available to process pleasure. In other words,
the listener can imagine the structure that provides the process that engenders
process pleasure. Although Butler's model focuses primarily on grouping
dissonance, I would also like to extend his model to include the multiplicities
of timbre, pitch or approximate register and the interplay between interlocking
riffs. I believe that most EDM tracks offer many perceptual 'points of
attention,' whether implied in minimalist textures or fully fleshed out in
thicker ones. Thus, looping allows the listener to plot pathways between these
points of attention, mapping out a landscape of shifting creation pleasure while
prolonging the process pleasure of an ever-changing same.
[5.3] To illustrate this idea, we turn to a track by Tony Rohr called "Baile
Conmigo" (or 'dance with me').(53) (Audio 2) This track is texturally quite
thick for a techno track, and offers a number of points of attention. Among
these, I would draw attention to the lower frequency range and the manner in
which the kick drum's pitch is inflected slightly after each attack: is that
indeed inflection, or the interference of a higher-pitched synth line? Also, in
the middle and treble range, note the interplay between interlocking patterns of
similar, but distinct timbres. Finally, I suggest following the trajectory of
the constant stream of sixteenth-note 'clicks', the frequency profile of which
shifts gradually upward and downward over a period of 4 measures of 4 quarter
notes or every 16 beats.
[6] PROCESS AS PLEASURE
[6.1] The idea that process could be pleasurable first came to me while
listening to Steve Reich's Piano Phase. To me, there is something uniquely
satisfying in the friction between the two out-of-phase pianists followed by the
'locking' effect when their pulse layers align. I then had further direction
from the work of Mark Butler, who characterizes the artistic production of
techno as "emphasiz[ing] process more than the construction of particular
musical objects".(54) Most recently, I found in the work of Karl Bühler a means
of articulating this pleasure in the concept of process pleasure (and creation
pleasure) explicated above. This is one path around the problem of
functionalism--of the view that process is pleasurable only insofar as it
produces a desire-fulfilling object (satiation pleasure). Repetitive processes
such as looping may serve pragmatic, extra-musical functions such as providing a
reasonably predictable framework for dancing or providing a particular sort of
feel that brings a crowd of dancers together at a club. However, they may also
emerge from and relate back to an aesthetic of process, thus generating pleasure
in addition to channeling the pleasures of dancing and socializing.
[6.2] With this concept in our minds, we can now turn to our next and last example: a selection from Akufen's 2002 album, My Way.(55) The track, "Deck the House," (Audio 3) and the entire album exhibit a unique compositional style, which requires a moment of explanation. Montréal-based Akufen, also known as Marc Leclair, gathered his musical materials for this album with a shortwave radio and a lot of time. Rather than sample complete hooks of songs or radio broadcasters, which would be illegal in almost any country, he uses brief slivers of songs, commercials, DJs' banter and static--most often less than a second long.(56) In "Deck the House," he weaves these microsamples together into a dizzying collage that illustrates my earlier notion of looping as prolongation of pleasure by its thick, multilayered texture and metric ambiguity (try locating the downbeat as this excerpt progresses). In addition to this, consider what I had argued earlier about process, accumulative form and the aural cues that help structure hearing and dancing. Imagine what opportunities arise for mastery and pleasure as the listener waits for the kick drum that signals the first complete 'arrival' or accumulation of the groove. For me, as one listener among many, a large part of the pleasure derived from listening to "Deck the House" stems directly from the pleasure of attending to the unfolding of a process both anticipated and unpredictable; inasmuch as process provides an opportunity for the manifestation of mastery that generates pleasure, challenging and surprising processes raise the stakes of mastery and offer higher "rewards."(57) Although Akufen/Leclair's taste for asymmetrical sequencing and metric ambiguity mirrors this unpredictability at the level of detailed surface, the fundamentally underdetermined nature of this structural unfolding permeates all EDM genres. As the process of looping creates this feeling of an ever-changing same, the question constantly arises: when will it change next, and how will it still remain the same?
[7] BEYOND ELECTRONIC DANCE MUSIC
[7.1] I imagine the overall shape of this essay to be one of
diffusion-->focus-->expansion. As I introduced the topic of repetition, we found
the discourse to be not only fraught, but also widely dispersed and
disarticulated. Indeed, there was and is no singular discourse of repetition, no
singular forum where all parties meet. Rather, the discourse and criticism on
repetition is a general and largely synthetic category for what is in fact a
vast constellation of discursive acts: solitary declarations, debate between
peers, and responses to imaginary interlocutors--and, much like a constellation,
I have endeavored to connect these "dots" of discourse into a larger picture.
[7.2] Discourse on repetition, both positive and negative, has largely relied on
some form of a reflection theory, looking for the strengths and weaknesses of
collective society or the individual psyche in repetitive structures. What I
have attempted to offer in its place is a model of what repetition does, for
whom and how. For these purposes I have revisited Karl Bühler's alternative to
Freud's repetition compulsion and adjusted them to better engage with the
experience of EDM: satiation pleasure, process pleasure, creation pleasure;
getting, doing, making. Although these categories of pleasure remain provisional
at most and their application to EDM is only exploratory, I hope to have
provided a preliminary vocabulary of tools for repetition that do not rely so
much on a metaphysics of ontology and identity.
[7.3] Of course, one does not need a kick drum to generate pleasure from
process, and I believe that one does not necessarily need to stay within the
confines of EDM, either. As my reference to Steve Reich's Piano Phase would
suggest, this approach to repetition and repetitive processes may also help to
explicate the manifold pleasures of listening to other musical traditions that
rely heavily on repetition, including minimalist art music, non-electronic dance
music, non-western classical traditions and a large proportion of folk
traditions. Indeed, Reich's essay on music as a "gradual process" articulates
similar emphases on process, process-oriented listening and control--but for the
minimalist art music of the late 60s and early 70s.(58) Also, I have restricted
my work here to the pleasures of listening, without much more than cursory
consideration of dancing. Although this artificial division and disembodiment of
listening from dancing greatly reduced the size of this essay, further work in
this direction is sorely needed.
[7.4] Furthermore, what I hope to offer here is not merely a broadly applicable model for repetition as an aesthetic practice. I am also striving to offer a rehabilitation and reevaluation of repetition that will hopefully rescue it from the categories of infantile regression, pathological compulsion, artlessness or a disproportionately dystopian/utopian allegory for social relations. If there is a beauty in the New, then there is also the question of a beautiful Same and, like repetition itself, the answer may be in the process of asking.
Comment on this article |
1. An earlier form of this paper was read under the same
title at the joint meeting of the American Musicological Society and the Society
for Music Theory, Seattle, 2004. I would like to thank Tony Rohr at Hidden
Agenda Records, Richie
Hawtin and Clark Warner at m_nus inc. / plus8 records ltd., and Marc Leclair and
Jon Berry at Regenerate Industries for generously granting permission for the
recorded examples included in this paper.
Return to text
2. Max Wechsler. "Wiederholung/Redundanz: Eine Kunstlerische Strategie Zwischen
Verdeutlichung Und Verwirrung," in Walter Fähndrich (ed.), Improvisation
III (Winterthur:
Amadeus, 1998), 58.
Return to text
3. Walter Benjamin, "The Work of Art in the Age of
Mechanical Reproduction." In Illuminations (London: Pimlico, 1999), 214.
Return to text
4. Susan McClary, Rap, Minimalism, and the Structures of
Time in Late Twentieth-Century Culture, Geske Lectures (Lincoln: College of Fine and
Performing Arts, University of Nebraska, 1998), 14. It is worth noting that,
although the drive for repetition has been pathologized in the form of Obsessive
Compulsive Disorder, the same cannot be said for the fear of or aversion to
repetition.
Return to text
5. Rousillon, René, Le plaisir et la répétition: Théorie du processus psychique
(Paris: Dunod, 2001), viii.
Return to text
6. Freud, Sigmund, Beyond the Pleasure Principle,
trans. J. Strachey (New
York: Liveright, 1950), 1. Original edition, 1920.
Return to text
7. Ibid, 58.
Return to text
8. Arnold Schoenberg, "Brahms Der Fortschrittliche," in
Stil Und Gedanke:
Aufs�tze Zur Musik (Frankfurt am Main: S. Fischer, 1976), 37. I have preserved
the gender-specificity of the abstract listening subject from Schoenberg's
writings to make a contrast with Freud's concern with both male and female
subjects.
Return to text
9. Arnold Schoenberg and Rudolf Stephan, Die Grundlagen Der Musikalischen
Komposition (Wien: Universal Edition, 1979), 20.
Return to text
10. Andreas Jacob, "Arnold Schonbergs Theoretische Schriften Über Funktion Und
Techniken Der Wiederholung," in Kathrin Eberl and Wolfgang Ruf (eds.),
Musikkonzepte-Konzepte Der Musikwissenschaft: Bericht Über Den Internationalen
Kongress Der Gesellschaft Für Musikforschung Halle (Saale) 1998, Bd 2: Freie
Referate (Kassel/New York: Bärenreiter, 2000), 572.
Return to text
11. This interpretation of Adorno's critique of repetition
is indebted to Ingrid Monson and Bernard Gendron. Bernard Gendron, "Theodor Adorno Meets the
Cadillacs," in Tania Modleski (ed.), Studies in Entertainment: Critical
Approaches to Mass Culture (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1986),
20-21; Ingrid T. Monson, "Riffs, Repetition, and Theories of Globalization,"
Ethnomusicology 43 (1999): 31-65.
Return to text
12. Adorno, Theodor W., "On Popular Music," in Susan H. Gillespie and Richard D.
Leppert (eds.), Essays on Music: Theodor W. Adorno (Berkeley: University of
California Press, 2002), 452-3. Original publication, 1941.
Return to text
13. Adorno, Theodor W., "Difficulties," in Essays on Music: Theodor W. Adorno,
667. Original publication, 1966.
Return to text
14. Adorno, Theodor W., "Wagner's Relevance for Today," in
Essays on Music: Theodor W. Adorno, 599. Original publication, 1963.
Return to text
15. Adorno, Theodor W., Philosophy of Modern Music, trans. Anne G. Mitchell
and Wesley G. Blomster (New York: Continuum, 2002), 135-191. Original
publication, 1958.
Return to text
16. Monson, 51.
Return to text
17. Ibid, 51-52.
Return to text
18. See: Rebecca Leydon, "Towards a Typology of Minimalist Tropes,"
Music
Theory Online 8.4 (2002); Carlo Migliaccio, "Ripetizione E Cambiamento in
Musica," De musica: Annuario in divenire 2 (1998); and Wechsler, 58-70.
Return to text
19. Leydon, 1-14.
Return to text
20. John Miller Chernoff, African Rhythm and African Sensibility: Aesthetics
and Social Action in African Musical Idioms (Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1979), 111-12.
Return to text
21. Steven Feld and Charles Keil (eds.), Music Grooves: Essays and Dialogues
(Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994).
Return to text
22. Steven Feld, "Sound Structure as Social Structure,"
Ethnomusicology 28
(1984): 383-407.
Return to text
23. Monson, 52.
Return to text
24. Veit Erlmann, "Communities of Style: Musical Figures of Black Diasporic
Identity," in Ingrid T. Monson (ed.), The African Diaspora: A Musical
Perspective (New York: Garland, 2000), 85-86.
Return to text
25. Henry Louis Gates Jr., The Signifying Monkey: A
Theory of Afro-American Literary Criticism (New York: Oxford University
Press, 1988).
Return to text
26. Erlmann, 86.
Return to text
27. Paul Kiparski, "Oral Poetry: Some Linguistic and Typological
Considerations," in Benjamin A. Stolz and Richard S. Shannon (eds.), Oral
Literature and the Formula (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan, 1976).
Return to text
28. Richard Middleton, "'Play It Again Sam': Some Notes on
the Productivity of Repetition in Popular Music," Popular Music 3 (1983):
239.
Return to text
29. Mark J. Butler, "Unlocking the Groove: Rhythm, Meter,
and Musical Design in Electronic Dance Music" (PhD, Indiana University, 2003),
69.
Return to text
30. Middleton, 240.
Return to text
31. Russell Potter, "Not the Same: Race, Repetition, and
Difference in Hip-Hop and Dance Music," in Thomas Swiss, John Sloop and Andrew
Herman (eds.), Mapping the Beat: Popular Music and Contemporary Theory
(Oxford: Blackwell, 1998), 31-46.
Return to text
32. Tricia Rose, Black Noise: Rap Music and Black
Culture in Contemporary America (Hanover, NH: Wesleyan University Press,
1994).
Return to text
33. See McClary, 24. This is not to say that these views
are to be discarded, but rather that further work must be done to reconcile
their theories with musical practice. An example of a step towards this might be Wim Mertens's work
on American minimalism: Mertens, Wim, American Minimal Music (London/New York:
Kahn & Averill/Broude, 1983), 118-124.
Return to text
34. Benjamin, 218.
Return to text
35. Bühler, Karl, Die Krise der Psychologie, 3rd ed. (Stuttgart: G. Fischer,
1965). Original edition, 1927.
Return to text
36. Ibid, 180-194.
Return to text
37. One might even extend this to tasks that efface their
products, e.g. the Zen Buddhist monastic practice of creating sand mandalas and then effacing them when
they are completed.
Return to text
38. Gould, Shirley and Heinz L. Ansbacher, "'Function Pleasure' in Adlerian
Psychotherapy," Journal of Individual Psychology 31/2 (1974): 150-57.
Return to text
39. One could productively "overstand" my terminology to question whether
"doing" stands at a level of abstraction between or above "receiving" and
"making;" as of yet, I am not prepared to take a stand on this issue.
Return to text
40. Bühler, 194.
Return to text
41. Williams, Linda, Hard Core: Power, Pleasure and the
"Frenzy of the Visible", Expanded Edition (Berkeley, CA: University of
California Press, 1999). BDSM is shorthand for an overlapping collection of sexual behaviors,
including Bondage, Discipline, Domination & Submission, and Sadism & Masochism
(or Sadomasochism).
Return to text
42. "Track" refers to a unit of music within EDM discourses in a manner similar
to "cut" or "joint" in hip-hop. This is generally preferable to labels such as
"song" more common in pop-rock discourses, which implies a song-structure and
use of vocals that rarely applies to EDM.
Return to text
43. The final example can also be considered form of "microhouse" (see [6.2n56]).
For a very useful (and often opinionated) overview of EDM genres and
sub-genres--including copious audio examples--see Ishkur, "Ishkur's Guide to
Electronic Music," in Digitally Imported FM,
http://www.di.fm/edmguide/edmguide.html (accessed Apr 1, 2005).
Return to text
44. Eugene Montague, "Moving to Music: A Theory of Sound
and Physical Action," (Ph.D. dissertation, University of Pennsylvania, 2001).
Return to text
45. Mark Spicer, "(Ac)Cumulative Form in Pop-Rock Music,"
twentieth-century
music 1 (2004): 33.
Return to text
46. This term may seem to be reminiscent of the title to Amiri Baraka's (LeRoi
Jones) essay, which seeks to build a history of black cultural (musical) forms
that emphasizes the continuity of the "changing same." However, my intention
here is rather to evoke the experience of listening to looping music: the
sensation of motion that does not move in a linear direction to a new place, but
returns to the same place--although that same place may have changed. c.f.
Baraka, Imamu Amiri (a.k.a. LeRoi Jones). "1966--The Changing Same (R&B and New
Black Music)," in Black Music (New York: W. Morrow, 1967), 180-211.
Return to text
47. Butler, 103.
Return to text
48. Ibid, 110.
Return to text
49. Peter J. Burkholder, All Made of Tunes: Charles
Ives and the Uses of Musical Borrowing (New Haven and London: Yale
University Press, 1995).
Return to text
50. Spicer, 29.
Return to text
51. Plastikman (a.k.a. Richie Hawtin), musik (NovaMute, 1994), CD.
Return to text
52. Mark J. Butler, "Hearing Kaleidoscopes: Embedded
Grouping Dissonance in Electronic Dance Music," presented at the Society for
Music Theory, Madison, WI 2003.
Return to text
53. Tony Rohr, "Baile Conmigo" (Tora! Tora! Tora!, [2002] 2004), 12" EP.
Return to text
54. Butler "Unlocking the Groove," 70.
Return to text
55. Akufen (a.k.a. Marc Leclair), My Way (Force Inc. Music Works, 2002), CD.
Return to text
56. Although Akufen's precise compositional technique (i.e. sampled radio-play
sliced into microsamples and reassembled into house music) is more or less
unique, the more general practice of microsampling informs a number of genres
that both precede and follow Akufen's work. For example, granular synthesis and
"microsound" styles have had a long history in electronic "art" music and more
recently in other electronic genres. Also, Akufen's 2002 release (see note 39)
marks the approximate time of an emergent "microhouse" genre, of which his work
is representative. Also related to this practice is the sample-heavy collage
work of artists such as DAT Politics, People Like Us, Matmos, The Soft Pink
Truth, MF Doom, DJ Danger Mouse, and Kid606.
Return to text
57. Provided that these processes are not so challenging
or surprising that they deny mastery.
Return to text
58. Reich, Steve, "Music as a Gradual Process (1968)," in
Paul Hillier (ed.), Writings on Music, 1965-2000 (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2002), 34-36.
Return to text
Copyright � 2005 by the Society for Music Theory. All rights reserved.
[1] Copyrights for individual items published in Music Theory Online (MTO) are held by their authors. Items appearing in MTO may be saved and stored in electronic or paper form, and may be shared among individuals for purposes of scholarly research or discussion, but may not be republished in any form, electronic or print, without prior, written permission from the author(s), and advance notification of the editors of MTO.
[2] Any redistributed form of items published in MTO must include the following information in a form appropriate to the medium in which the items are to appear:
This item appeared in Music Theory Online in [VOLUME #, ISSUE #] on [DAY/MONTH/YEAR]. It was authored by [FULL NAME, EMAIL ADDRESS], with whose written permission it is reprinted here.
[3] Libraries may archive issues of MTO in electronic or paper form for public access so long as each issue is stored in its entirety, and no access fee is charged. Exceptions to these requirements must be approved in writing by the editors of MTO, who will act in accordance with the decisions of the Society for Music Theory.
This document and all portions thereof are protected by U.S. and international copyright laws. Material contained herein may be copied and/or distributed for research purposes only.
Prepared by Brent Yorgason, Managing Editor
Updated
24 October 2005