ABSTRACT: In this commentary, I will first clear the air of a criticism Walker has made of Brown's "Adrift on Neurath's Boat." [in MTO 2.2 (Ed.)] Secondly, I will look at what issues arise when naturalizing music theory, by allowing revisions. Thirdly, I will critically address two proposals made by Brown regarding testing theories and the connection between aesthetic and nonaesthetic properties. Finally, I will consider the ramifications of Brown and Dempster's scientific model of music theory and discuss alternatives to this model.
[1.2] Walker's criticism of Brown is unfounded and stems from Walker's misreading of Quine. Brown does not equate naturalizing music theory with putting observational (synthetic) and foundational (analytic) statements on the same footing. Rather, Brown makes the point, taken from Quine's view of science, that observational statements differ from foundational ones in degree but not in kind. Consider this example: "The distribution of interval-class invariant pc-set classes contributes to organic coherence in Webern's music." In one context, this statement would be considered observational, in another context it would be foundational. In other words: in one case the analyst might try to analyze and explicate Webern's pitch organization (observational), while in another case, assumptions concerning Webern's pitch organization may enter into the analysis of some other aspect of his music -- or perhaps another composer's music (foundational).
[1.3] Quine's central contention is that "all statements are revisable":
there is no strict dichotomy between observational statements
(synthetic/revisable) and foundational statements
(analytic/non-revisable). Whether a statement is observational or
foundational is not a philosophical question. It's an empirical
question. It's a question about how humans reason. Therefore, it's a
question for behavioral psychology, which is a natural science --
hence the term naturalized.
[1.4] When there's friction between observations and foundational
principles, it may be a good idea to revise foundational
principles. When faced with such friction, we can amend a theory, or
theories, in various places to accommodate it. Of course, our
tendency is to disturb the entire system of theories as little as
possible (call it laziness). So, we focus our revisions upon the
specific observational statements which aroused the friction.
[2.2] Don't think music theory is alone with these dilemmas: detailed,
is analogous to what statisticians call validity; satisfying, is
analogous to what they call sensitivity. Validity is, roughly, the
proportion of data values included in a statistical procedure
(detailed). Sensitivity is the interpretive precision allowed by the
included data values (satisfying). Increasing validity decreases
sensitivity, and vice-versa. A statistical procedure is called
robust if it retains validity and sensitivity when applied to data
sets which differ from the expected profile (e.g. classes of music to
which we didn't expect to apply the analytic procedure).
[5.2] What about testing theories and analyses? I presume that testing theories and analyses means taking aim at dubious claims about a particular musical work or a particular dimension (e.g. the role of pc-set structures) of a body of musical works (e.g. music in the twelve-pitched equal tempered system).
[5.3] In an analysis, we inevitably highlight selected nonaesthetic properties which we claim have aesthetic significance in the global interpretation of the work. Let's assume our theories and analyses are logically consistent and not counterfactual. We may then question the claims by asking how, why, and how much are these nonaesthetic properties significant?
[5.4] We might deem a nonaesthetic property significant because it is a
contextual anomaly with respect to analogous contexts in other musical
works or in the same work. We can debunk such a claim of aesthetic
significance by demonstrating that, in fact, the nonaesthetic property
in question is a consequence of the musical system or the
compositional technique. Babbitt demonstrates how nonaesthetic
properties of a musical work which seem to be anomalous, can actually
be consequences of the twelve-tone system. In one instance, he
discusses the significance of Stravinsky's choice of the 6-9 hexachord
in his "Variations." Babbitt demonstrates that the inversional
relationship between the "verticals" resulting from order rotations is
not due to properties peculiar to the 6-9 hexachord. Rather it is a
consequence of the order rotation procedure.
[5.5] We may also deem a nonaesthetic property aesthetically
significant because it is easily heard. Suppose the property in
question is a similarity between two particular sonorities in the
musical work. We note that the two sonorities contain the same
interval classes. Brown would have us refer to psychoacoustic test
results to decide how easy it is to hear that two sonorities contain
the same interval classes. However, such psychoacoustic experiments
inevitably use out-of-context listening examples. It's not hard to
imagine that, in an actual musical context, the interval content of
set-classes is reinforced if it occurs first as a melody and then
as a harmony, or vice-versa.
[5.6] Brown's medicine seems innocuous (even tasteless) at first glance because it purports to help us understand aesthetic properties better. (That sounds OK. It's already part of the agenda of music theory, so maybe Brown and Dempster's scientific model is compatible with the aesthetic aims of music theory.) In fact, understanding aesthetic concepts is one of his main ingredients: Brown emphasizes "the need to find law-like relationships not only among aesthetic properties, but also between aesthetic and nonaesthetic properties."
[5.7] Finding law-like relationships between aesthetic and nonaesthetic
properties is an enterprise which might seem sensible at first
glance. But it's not. Frank Sibley explained the problem, in a general
way in his essay "Aesthetic Concepts."
[5.8] Generally, we may say that the presence of a nonaesthetic
property can be determined by some mechanical procedure, whether
simple (e.g. observing the notes in a chord) or involved (e.g.
invariance matrices and pc-similarity measures). On the other hand,
the application of an aesthetic term is anything but mechanical.
Sibley explains "the making of such judgments as these requires the
exercise of taste, perceptiveness, or sensitivity, of aesthetic
discrimination or appreciation. One would not say this of the first
group, [nonaesthetic terms]."
[5.9] In order to find law-like relationships between aesthetic and nonaesthetic properties, we must assume that the mere presence of certain nonaesthetic properties in a musical work can determine whether or not a certain aesthetic term is appropriate for that work, dimension of the work, or section of the work. We're looking for laws of appropriateness for saying that a musical work has such-and-such an aesthetic property?
[5.10] Often we support the application of an aesthetic term by
referring to other aesthetic properties which we claim are present in
the musical work. However, in other instances we support the
application of an aesthetic term by referring to purely nonaesthetic
properties which are present. We may eagerly jump to the conclusion
(as Brown does) that the dependence of aesthetic properties on
nonaesthetic properties can be formulated into rules or laws. Not
so. "[T]here are no nonaesthetic features which service in any
circumstances as logically sufficient conditions for applying
aesthetic terms. Aesthetic or taste concepts are not in this
respect condition-governed at all."
[5.11] Many readers will know that Wittgenstein, among others,
illustrated that familiar everyday concepts are governed only loosely
by conditions, not strictly by necessary-and-sufficient
conditions.
[5.12] When there are no necessary-and-sufficient conditions for
applying an everyday concept, there are usually relevant features
which, if present, warrant the use the concept. For example, in
claiming that someone is intelligent we can start to list features
which are relevant to intelligence. Such relevant features are
"ability to grasp and follow various kinds of instructions, ability to
master facts and marshal evidence, ability to solve mathematical or
chess problems," etc.
[5.13] We can even accept that with everyday terms, such as
intelligence, the mere reporting of the presence of some group of
features will unquestioningly justify the use of the term. "We are
able to say 'If it is true he can do this, and that, and the other,
then one just cannot deny that he is intelligent.'"
[5.14] Brown is asking us to seek law-like relationships between aesthetic properties and nonaesthetic properties -- prediction is his game. So he must be asking us to assume that the mere presence of certain nonaesthetic properties in a musical work can determine the aptness of applying a certain aesthetic term to the work, dimension of the work, or section of the work. Beware -- the consumption of this assumption might cause indigestion.
[5.15] Allow me to introduce SMT (scientific music theorist). Suppose SMT gathers together paradigm cases of musical works, or excerpts, which are said to have a particular aesthetic property. Then, using these paradigm musical examples as stimuli, SMT carries out psycho-acoustic, neurobiological, and cognitive psychological experiments (using musicians and nonmusicians as subjects). Then SMT analyzes the data; he correlates the responses of the study subjects with nonaesthetic properties found in our paradigm musical examples. Through this process SMT develops a predictive model, one that provides laws describing the dependence of a particular aesthetic property on the presence of particular nonaesthetic properties. He can then, as an analyst, apply such models, analyzing other musical works, ascribing aesthetic properties to these musical works based on an assemblage of information regarding nonaesthetic properties they exhibit.
[5.16] It is now time for SMT to become SMA (scientific music analyst)
in order to demonstrate the application of his research. Now, imagine
behind a curtain is a musical work. In front of the curtain is
SMA. SMA stands before an audience of other music analysts, theorists,
performers, and educated music enthusiasts. SMA knows his audience
well; he knows they have a predilection for musical works deemed
organically coherent. SMA is prepared to present an analysis of the
musical work to his audience, to convince them that the work is indeed
organically coherent. He also knows that organic coherence is not
just a matter of nonaesthetic properties, but a matter of aesthetic
ones as well. SMA has never actually heard the musical work behind
the curtain, nor seen the score; his audience is equally unfamiliar
with the musical work. But SMA fears not: he is equipped with laws,
derived from empirical experiments, predicting the dependence of
aesthetic properties on nonaesthetic properties. His audience is
equally knowledgeable of these empirically tested laws (they do their
homework). SMA has chosen his musical specimen by the following
process: He has a host of musical scores, with accompanying audio
recordings, encoded in all detail and stored in a database. SMA has
developed a complex querying program which probes the musical works in
the database to find works which have the requisite combination of
nonaesthetic properties to have certain aesthetic properties, which
are in turn required in order to make his analysis convincing.
[5.17] The absurdity of this music-behind-the-curtain scenario points to
the problem with devising laws defining the relationships between
nonaesthetic properties and aesthetic properties: to devise such laws
is simply to turn the aesthetic terms into nonaesthetic terms.
Furthermore, the notion that music analyses can proceed and be
understood without first hand experience of the particular musical
work, serves as a kind of unintentional Ursatz of Brown and Dempster's
program. In "The Scientific Image of Music Theory" Brown and Dempster
rhetorically asked the questions "[H]ow are analytical prescriptions
justified? Should a naive listener simply place faith in the
authority of some particular analyst? If so, which one?," and "[H]ow
can we be sure that the judgments of one self-professed connoisseur
are more trustworthy than those of another?"
[6.2] As the smoke clears, it looks like Brown and Dempster thought, that by asking us to be more scientific, they were asking us to grow stronger roots for the tree that Boretz, Rahn, and Babbitt have already grown (music theory as a science). But in fact, Brown and Dempster are asking us to grow a whole new tree, with completely different roots (predictive aims of empirical science) -- roots which neither Boretz, Rahn, Babbitt, nor the rest of music theory ever had.
[6.3] Brown and Dempster direct deserved attention to the notion that empirical science could be extremely fruitful for music theory: psycho-acoustics, cognitive psychology, and neurobiology can be invaluable for helping us understand how we hear, remember, and physically respond to music. But that says nothing about choosing empirical scientific aims (prediction) instead of critical aesthetic aims. Contrary to what Brown and Dempster assumed, there is no inconsistency in enlisting the study of psycho-acoustics, cognitive psychology, and neurobiology to pursue critical aesthetic aims. There is no inconsistency in choosing a precise language of discourse to pursue critical aesthetic aims. There is no inconsistency in probing nonaesthetic properties with computerized techniques and statistical correlation to pursue critical aesthetic aims.
[7.2] In this aesthetic model, a music analysis should offer the reader
a perspective by, in effect, saying "If you look at it this way you
will see the aesthetic property I see" (organic coherence, etc.). We
tacitly ask the reader to observe, from the score, the aesthetic (and
nonaesthetic) properties discussed in the analysis. We mention
nonaesthetic properties to support our claim of an aesthetic property;
we guide the reader to the proper perspective to observe the aesthetic
property first hand. A music analysis, like any critical analysis,
serves to direct attention to what is not obvious to casual or
uninstructed inspection; it doesn't substitute for first hand
experience of the particular musical work. The analyst's presentation
"will always reflect a critical attitude toward the piece."
1. Jonathan Walker, posting to mto-talk@societymusictheory.org
of 3/3/96: 2.
Return to text
2. Willard V.O. Quine, "Epistemology Naturalized," Ontological
Relativity (New York: Columbia University Press, 1969): 83.
Return to text
3. Willard V.O. Quine, "Two Dogmas," in From a Logical Point of
View (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1961/1980): 44.
Return to text
4. Quine, "Two Dogmas," 42.
Return to text
5. Jonathan Walker, posting to mto-talk@societymusictheory.org
of 3/3/96: 5.
Return to text
6. See, for example, Lambert Koopmans An Introduction to
Contemporary Statistics (Boston: Duxbury Press, 1981): 224-233.
Return to text
7. Brown and Dempster point out that Boretz, Rahn, and Babbitt
cannot sustain the Deductive-Nomonological model proposed by
Hempel. See Brown and Dempster, "The Scientific Image of Music
Theory," Journal of Music Theory 33 (1989): 65-106.
Return to text
8. Babbitt has in several places emphasized a scientific approach to musical problems. But his allusions to "prediction" are not concerned with predicting, per se, the behavior of music in aesthetic terms. Rather, his concerns are the inherent formal properties of the twelve-pitch equal tempered system and more specifically the twelve-tone system. He has emphasized that investigation of these properties can serve not only to uncover resources for the composer, but also to forecast possible attributes to be observed in future musical works. The investigation Babbitt has in mind is directly concerned only with nonaesthetic properties, not empirically driven prediction of aesthetic properties. Milton Babbitt, "The Structure and Function of Music Theory," in Boretz & Cone, ed., Perspectives on Contemporary Music Theory (New York: Norton, 1972): 14, 20.
According to Rahn, "The game played by music theorists emphasizes communication, not segregation or prediction." John Rahn, "Notes on Methodology in Music Theory," Journal of Music Theory 33 (1989): 150.
Boretz emphasizes that analysis serves to demonstrate the
coherence of a musical work by showing the multiplicity of
significant relationships between pitches.
Benjamin Boretz, "Meta-variations," Perspectives of New Music Part 2, 8/2
(1970): 64, Part 3/1,9/1 (1970): 24, Part 3/2, 9/2 (1971): 258.
Return to text
9. Matthew Brown, "Adrift on Neurath's Boat," Music Theory
Online 2.2 (1996): 16.
Return to text
10. Milton Babbitt, "Contemporary Music Composition and Music
Theory as Contemporary Intellectual History," in Perspectives in
Musicology (New York: Norton, 1972): 165-67. For a discussion
of the probabilistic significance of the Rp pc-set class
similarity relation see Allen Forte, The Structure of Atonal
Music (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1973): 47, 49.
Return to text
11. Babbitt, "Contemporary Music Composition and Music Theory as
Contemporary Intellectual History," 165-67.
Return to text
12. The contextual significance of harmonic (vertical) and
melodic (horizontal) presentations of the same set class in the
second movement of Webern's Concerto Op.24 are discussed by
Christopher Hasty, "Segmentation and Process in Post-Tonal
Music," Music Theory Spectrum 3 (1981): 54-73.
Return to text
13. Frank Sibley, "Aesthetic Concepts," Philosophical Review
67 (1959): 421-450.
Return to text
14. Sibley, 421.
Return to text
15. Sibley, 424.
Return to text
16. Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, 3rd ed.
(New York: Macmillan Publishing Co.): 33-40.
Return to text
17. Sibley, 425-26.
Return to text
18. Sibley, 426.
Return to text
19. Computer aided analysis has indeed been insightful regarding
structural relationships of nonaesthetic properties and their
correlation to possible segmentations (i.e. No criticism of
computer aided analysis is intended.) See, for example James
Tenney and Larry Polansky, "Temporal Gestalt Perception in Music,"
Journal of Music Theory 24/2 (1980): 205-242. See also Yayoi
Uno and Roland Hubscher, "Temporal-Gestalt Segmentation,"
Computers in Music Research 5 (1995): 1-38.
Return to text
20. Matthew Brown and Douglas Dempster, "The Scientific Image of
Music Theory," Journal of Music Theory 33 (1989): 92, 96.
Return to text
21. Quine, "Two Dogmas," 44.
Return to text
22.. David Lewin, "Behind the Beyond," Perspectives of New
Music 7/2 (1969): 63.
Return to text
23. In fact, music theory can actually determine, or at least
influence, directions which music composition takes. Milton
Babbitt's theoretical work taken together with his own
compositional output and that of others is a good example of
this phenomenon.
Return to text
24. Lewin, "Behind the Beyond," 63.
Return to text
25. Ibid.
Return to text
26. See, for example, Jane Piper Clendinning, "The Pattern-
Meccanico Compositions of Gyorgy Ligeti," Perspectives of New
Music 31/1 (1993): 192-234.
Return to text
[2] Any redistributed form of items published in MTO must include the following information in a form appropriate to the medium in which the items are to appear:
This item appeared in Music Theory Online in [VOLUME #, ISSUE #] on [DAY/MONTH/YEAR]. It was authored by [FULL NAME, EMAIL ADDRESS], with whose written permission it is reprinted here.
[3] Libraries may archive issues of MTO in electronic or paper form for public access so long as each issue is stored in its entirety, and no access fee is charged. Exceptions to these requirements must be approved in writing by the editors of MTO, who will act in accordance with the decisions of the Society for Music Theory.
This document and all portions thereof are protected by U.S. and international copyright laws. Material contained herein may be copied and/or distributed for research purposes only.